-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 7
/
54A20-ProofOfAlternativeCharacterizationOfUltrafilter.tex
69 lines (56 loc) · 5.37 KB
/
54A20-ProofOfAlternativeCharacterizationOfUltrafilter.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
\documentclass[12pt]{article}
\usepackage{pmmeta}
\pmcanonicalname{ProofOfAlternativeCharacterizationOfUltrafilter}
\pmcreated{2013-03-22 14:42:23}
\pmmodified{2013-03-22 14:42:23}
\pmowner{rspuzio}{6075}
\pmmodifier{rspuzio}{6075}
\pmtitle{proof of alternative characterization of ultrafilter}
\pmrecord{16}{36325}
\pmprivacy{1}
\pmauthor{rspuzio}{6075}
\pmtype{Proof}
\pmcomment{trigger rebuild}
\pmclassification{msc}{54A20}
\endmetadata
% this is the default PlanetMath preamble. as your knowledge
% of TeX increases, you will probably want to edit this, but
% it should be fine as is for beginners.
% almost certainly you want these
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{amsmath}
\usepackage{amsfonts}
% used for TeXing text within eps files
%\usepackage{psfrag}
% need this for including graphics (\includegraphics)
%\usepackage{graphicx}
% for neatly defining theorems and propositions
%\usepackage{amsthm}
% making logically defined graphics
%%%\usepackage{xypic}
% there are many more packages, add them here as you need them
% define commands here
\begin{document}
\paragraph {Proof that $A \coprod B = X$ implies $A \in \mathcal{U}$ or $B \in \mathcal{U}$}
Once we show that $A \notin \mathcal{U}$ implies $B \notin \mathcal{U}$, this result will follow immediately.
On the one hand, suppose that $A \notin \mathcal{U}$ and that there exists a $C \in \mathcal{U}$ such that $A \cap C$ is empty. Then $C \subseteq B$. Since $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter and $C \in \mathcal{U}$, this implies that $B \in \mathcal{U}$.
On the other hand, suppose that $A \notin \mathcal{U}$ and that $A \cap C$ is not empty for any $C$ in $\mathcal{U}$. Then $\{A\} \cup \mathcal{U}$ would be a filter subbasis. The filter which it would generate would be finer than $\mathcal{U}$. The fact that $\mathcal{U}$ is an ultrafilter means that there exists no filter finer than $\mathcal{U}$. This contradiction shows that, if $A \notin \mathcal{U}$, then there exists a $C$ such that $A \cap C$ is empty. But this would imply that $C \subseteq B$ which, in turn would imply that $B \in \mathcal{U}$.
\paragraph{ Proof that $\mathcal{U}$ is an ultrafilter.}
Assume that $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter, but not an ultrafilter and that $A \coprod B = X$ implies $A \in \mathcal{U}$ or $B \in \mathcal{U}$. Since $\mathcal{U}$ is not an ultrafilter, there must exist filter $\mathcal{U}'$ which is strictly finer. Hence there must exist $A \in \mathcal{U}'$ such that $A \notin \mathcal{U}$. Set $B = X \setminus A$. Since $A \coprod B = X$ and $A \notin \mathcal{U}$, it follows that $B \in \mathcal{U}$. Since $\mathcal{U} \subset \mathcal{U}'$, it is also the case that $B \in \mathcal{U}'$. But $A \in \mathcal{U}'$ as well; since $\mathcal{U}'$ is a filter, $A \cap B \in \mathcal{U}'$. This is impossible because $A \cap B \in \mathcal{U}'$ is empty. Therefore, no such filter $\mathcal{U}'$ can exist and $\mathcal{U}$ must be an ultrafilter.
\paragraph{ Proof of generalization to $A \cup B = X$}
On the one hand, since $A \cup B = X$ implies $A \coprod B = X$, the condition $A \cup B = X \Rightarrow A \in \mathcal{U} \vee B\in \mathcal{U}$ will also imply that $\mathcal{U}$ is an ultrafilter.
On the other hand, if $A \cup B = X$, there must exists $A' \subseteq A$ and $B' \subseteq B$ such that $A' \coprod B' = X$. If $\mathcal{U}$ is assumed to be a filter, $A' \in \mathcal{U}$ implies that $A \in \mathcal{U}$. Likewise, $B' \in \mathcal{U}$ implies that $B \in \mathcal{U}$. Hence, if $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter such that $A \cup B = X$ implies that either $A \in \mathcal{U}$ or $B \in \mathcal{U}$, then $\mathcal{U}$ is an ultrafilter.
\paragraph {Proof of first proposition regarding finite unions}
Let $B_j = \coprod_{i=1}^j A_i$ and let $C_j = \coprod_{i=j+1}^n A_i$. For each $i$ between $1$ and $n-1$, we have $B_i \coprod C_i = X$. Hence, either $B_i \in \mathcal{U}$ or $C_i \in \mathcal{U}$ for each $i$ between $1$ and $n-1$. Next, consider three possibilities:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $B_1 \in \mathcal{U}$: Since $B_1 = A_1$, it follows that $A_1 \in \mathcal{U}$.
\item $B_{n-1} \notin \mathcal{U}$: Since $B_{n-1} \coprod C_{n-1} = X$, it follows that $C_{n-1} \in \mathcal{U}$. Because $C_{n-1} = A_n$, it follows that $A_n \in \mathcal{U}$.
\item $B_1 \notin \mathcal{U}$ and $B_{n-1} \in \mathcal{U}$: There must exist an $i \in \{2, \ldots, n-1\}$ such that $B_{i-1} \notin \mathcal{U}$ and $B_i \in \mathcal{U}$. Since $B_{i-1} \notin \mathcal{U}$, $C_{i-1} \in \mathcal{U}$.
Since $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter, $C_{i-1} \cap B_i \in \mathcal{U}$. But also $C_{i-1} \cap B_i = A_i$ which implies that $A_i \in \mathcal{U}$.
\end{enumerate}
This examination of cases shows that if $\coprod_{i=1}^n A_i = X$, then there must exist an $i$ such that $A_i \in \mathcal{U}$. It is also easy to see that this $i$ is unique --- If $A_i \in \mathcal{U}$ and $A_j \in \mathcal{U}$ and $i \ne j$, then $A_i \cap A_j = \emptyset$, but this cannot be the case since $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter.
\paragraph {Proof of second proposition regarding finite unions}
There exist sets $A'_i$ such that $A'_i \subseteq A_i$ and $\coprod_{i=1}^n A_i = X$. By the result just proven, there exists an $i$ such that $A'_i \in \mathcal{U}$. Since $\mathcal{U}$ is a filter, $A'_i \in \mathcal{U}$ implies $A_i \in \mathcal{U}$. Note that we can no longer assert that $i$ is unique because the $A_i$'s no longer are required to be pairwise disjoint.
%%%%%
%%%%%
\end{document}