-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
BufferStockTheory.tex
2327 lines (2025 loc) · 134 KB
/
BufferStockTheory.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
% Modified for JHU Class
\input{./econtexRoot}\input{\econtexRoot/econtexPaths}\documentclass[titlepage]{\econtex}\providecommand{\texname}{BufferStockTheory}
\providecommand{\EqDir}{Equations}
\providecommand{\FigDir}{Figures}
\renewcommand{\FigDir}{Code/Python/Figures}
\providecommand{\CodeDir}{Code}
\providecommand{\CalibrationDir}{Calibration}
\providecommand{\TableDir}{Tables}
\providecommand{\ApndxDir}{Appendices}
\usepackage{subfiles}
\providecommand{\onlyinsubfile}{}
\providecommand{\notinsubfile}{}
\renewcommand{\onlyinsubfile}[1]{}
\renewcommand{\notinsubfile}[1]{#1}
\usepackage{\econtexSetup}\usepackage{\econtexShortcuts}\usepackage{makecell}
\provideboolean{Shorter}
\setboolean{Shorter}{true}
\setboolean{Shorter}{false}
\providecommand{\ShorterYN}{\ifthenelse{\boolean{Shorter}}}
\usepackage{rotating}\usepackage{subfigure}
\hypersetup{pdfauthor={Christopher D. Carroll <[email protected]>},
pdftitle={Theoretical Foundations of Buffer Stock Saving},
pdfkeywords={Precautionary saving, buffer-stock saving, consumption, marginal propensity to consume, permanent income hypothesis},
pdfcreator = {[email protected]}
}
\begin{document}\bibliographystyle{\econtexBibStyle}
\renewcommand{\onlyinsubfile}[1]{}\renewcommand{\notinsubfile}[1]{#1}
\hfill{\tiny \texname.tex, \today}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\texname.title}
Theoretical Foundations of Buffer Stock Saving
\end{verbatimwrite}
\title{Theoretical Foundations of \\ Buffer Stock Saving}
\author{Matthew V. Zahn\authNum}
\keywords{Precautionary saving, buffer stock saving, marginal propensity to consume, permanent income hypothesis}
\jelclass{D81, D91, E21}
\maketitle
\hypertarget{abstract}{}
\begin{abstract}
This paper builds theoretical foundations for rigorous and intuitive understanding of `buffer stock' saving models, pairing each theoretical result with a quantitative exploration. After describing conditions under which the consumption function converges, the paper shows that `target' saving behavior, which defines buffer stock saving, arises only under conditions strictly stronger than those that guarantee convergence of the consumption and value functions. It also shows that average consumption growth equals average income growth in a small open economy populated by buffer stock savers. Together, the (provided) numerical tools and (proven) analytical results constitute a comprehensive toolkit for understanding buffer stock models.
\end{abstract}
\begin{small}
\parbox{\textwidth}{
\begin{center}
\begin{tabbing}
\texttt{~Archive:~} \= \= \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/BufferStockTheory.zip} \kill \\ %
\texttt{~~~~~PDF:~} \> \> \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/BufferStockTheory.pdf} \\
\texttt{~~Slides:~} \> \> \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/BufferStockTheory-Slides.pdf} \\
\texttt{~~~~~Web:~} \> \> \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/BufferStockTheory/} \\
\texttt{~~GitHub:~} \> \> \url{http://github.com/llorracc/BufferStockTheory} \\
\texttt{~~~~~~~~~~} \> \> \textit{(In GitHub repo, see \texttt{/Code} for tools for solving and simulating the model)} \\
\end{tabbing}
\end{center}
\href{https://colab.research.google.com/github/llorracc/BufferStockTheory/blob/master/Code/Python/BufferStockTheory.ipynb}{CLICK HERE} for an interactive \href{https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Project\_Jupyter\#Jupyter_Notebook}{Jupyter Notebook} that uses the \href{https://econ-ark/HARK}{Econ-ARK/HARK} toolkit to produce all of the paper's figures (warning: it may take several minutes to launch)}
\end{small}
\begin{authorsinfo}
\name{Contact: \href{mailto:[email protected]}{\texttt{[email protected]}}, Department of Economics, 590 Wyman Hall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21218, \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll}, and National Bureau of Economic Research.}
\end{authorsinfo}
\thanks{All numerical results herein were produced using the \href{https://econ-ark/HARK}{Econ-ARK/HARK} toolkit, which can be cited as in our references (\cite{carroll_et_al-proc-scipy-2018}); for further reference options see \href{https://econ-ark.org/acknowledging/}{Acknowleding Econ-ARK}. Thanks to James Feigenbaum, Joseph Kaboski, Miles Kimball, Qingyin Ma, Misuzu Otsuka, Damiano Sandri, John Stachurski, Adam Szeidl, Metin Uyanik, Weifeng Wu,
and Jiaxiong Yao for comments on earlier versions of this paper, John Boyd for help
in applying his weighted contraction mapping theorem, Ryoji
Hiraguchi for extraordinary mathematical insight that improved the
paper greatly, David Zervos for early guidance to the literature,
and participants in a seminar at Johns Hopkins University and a
presentation at the 2009 meetings of the Society of Economic
Dynamics for their insights.}
\titlepagefinish
\newtheorem{defn}{Definition}
\newtheorem{theorem}{Theorem}
\hypertarget{Introduction}{}
\section{Introduction}
\label{sec:intro}
In the presence of empirically realistic transitory and permanent shocks to income \textit{a la} \cite{friedmanATheory}, only one additional ingredient is required to define a testable model of optimal consumption choice: A utility specification. Quantitative modelers usually assume constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) utility with geometric discounting, because with those choices the model generates results reasonably in accord with the available evidence.
But the theoretical literature has mostly studied models that are more complex -- say, with a liquidity constraint or consumption floor -- because standard contraction mapping theorems (beginning with \cite{bellmanDynamicProgramming} and including those of Stokey et.~al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods}) cannot be applied when the utility function is unbounded (like CRRA - see the end of \hyperlink{DiffFromLit}{section \ref{subsec:Setup}} for details).\footnote{It is unclear whether newer methods such as those of \cite{mnUnique}) could overcome this problem, or how difficult it would be to do so; but in any case this particular problem does not seem to have been tackled by those methods or any others.}
Numerical solutions to such problems have become widespread following Zeldes~\citeyearpar{zeldesStochastic}, without too much attention to theoretical underpinnings because the conclusions being sought are quantitative. But without theoretical underpinnings, the `black box' character of numerical solutions makes it difficult to build intuition for how results might change with changes in the structure or calibration of the model. Indeed, without such theory, it can be difficult even to check whether a computational solution is correct.
For example, numerical solutions typically indicate the existence of a target level of nonhuman wealth (`cash' for short). Carroll~\citeyearpar{carrollBrookings,carrollBSLCPIH} showed that target saving behavior arises under plausible parameter values for both infinite and finite horizon models. Gourinchas and Parker~\citeyearpar{gpLifeCycle} estimate that for the mean household, buffer stock behavior characterizes behavior from age 25 until around age 40-45; using the same model with different data Cagetti~\citeyearpar{cagettiWprofiles} finds target saving behavior into the 50s for the median household. Such target saving plays a key role in understanding the main results of the recent heterogeneous agent macroeconomics literature, including, for example, the insight in \cite{kmpHandbook} that explains why, during the Great Recession, middle-class consumers cut their consumption more than the poor or the rich. Similar behavior characterizes the `wealthy hand-to-mouth' in \cite{kaplanViolanteWeidner_wealthyH2M}, who have plenty of illiquid assets but liquid assets that are low relative to their target levels. Despite the centrality of the mechanism, none of these papers provides a characterization of the circumstances under which target saving will emerge.
The paper's main technical contributions are to articulate the (surprisingly loose) conditions under which the problem defines a contraction mapping with a nondegenerate consumption function, and conditions under which the resulting consumption function a implies expstence of a `target' wealth-to-permanent-income ratio. (This is the sense in which the paper studies the class of `buffer stock' saving models.) The key condition required for target saving is that the model's parameters need to satisfy a ``Growth Impatience Condition'' (equation \eqref{eq:GIC}) which relates preferences to the predictable growth rate of income.
The paper also provides analytical foundations for other results that have become familiar from the numerical literature. All theoretical conclusions are paired with numerically computed illustrations (using an open-source toolkit available from the \href{https://github.com/econ-ark/REMARK/blob/master/REMARKs/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory.ipynb}{Econ-ARK} project). All of the insights of this paper are instantiated in the toolkit, which algorithmically flags parametric choices under which a problem fails to define a contraction mapping, under which a target level of wealth does not exist, or under which the solution is otherwise degenerate.
The paper proceeds in three parts.
The first part articulates the conditions required for the problem to define a unique nondegenerate limiting consumption function, and discusses the relation of the paper's model to models previously considered in the literature. The required conditions turn out to be interestingly parallel to those required for the liquidity constrained perfect foresight model; that parallel is explored and explained. Next, the paper derives some limiting properties of the consumption function as cash approaches infinity and as it approaches its lower bound, and the theorem is proven explaining when the problem defines a contraction mapping. Finally, a related class of commonly-used models (exemplified by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}) is shown to constitute a particular limit of this paper's more general model.
The \hyperlink{AnalysisoftheConvergedConsumptionFunction}{next section} examines five key properties of the model. First, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToInfty}{cash approaches infinity} the expected growth rate of consumption and the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) converge to their values in the perfect foresight case. Second, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToZero}{cash approaches zero} the expected growth rate of consumption approaches infinity, and the MPC approaches a simple analytical limit. Third, if the consumer is `growth impatient,' a \hyperlink{onetarget}{unique target cash-to-permanent-income ratio} will exist. Fourth, at the target cash ratio, the \hyperlink{cGroLTpGro}{expected growth rate of consumption} is slightly less than the expected growth rate of permanent noncapital income. Finally, the expected growth rate of consumption \hyperlink{dcgdxneg}{is declining in the level of cash}. The first four propositions are proven under general assumptions about parameter values; the last is shown to hold if there are no transitory shocks, but may fail in extreme cases if there are both transitory and permanent shocks.
Szeidl~\citeyearpar{szeidlInvariant} has shown that such an economy will be characterized by stable invariant distributions for the consumption ratio, the wealth ratio, and other variables.\footnote{Szeidl's proof supplants the analysis in an earlier draft of this paper, which conjectured that such a result held and provided supportive simulation evidence.} Using Szeidl's result, the final section discusses conditions under which, even with a fixed aggregate interest rate that differs from the time preference rate, an economy populated by buffer stock consumers converges to a balanced growth equilibrium in which the growth rate of consumption tends toward the (exogenous) growth rate of permanent income.
\hypertarget{The-Problem}{}
\section{The Problem}
\subsection{Setup}
\label{subsec:Setup}
The consumer solves an optimization problem from period
$t$ until the end of life at $T$ defined by the objective
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/supfn.tex}
\begin{eqnarray}
\label{eq:supfn}
\max~ \Ex_{t}\left[\sum_{n=0}^{T-t} \DiscFac^{n} \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t+n})\right]
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/supfn.tex}
where
$\uFunc(\bullet)=\bullet^{1-\CRRA}/(1-\CRRA)$ is a constant relative
risk aversion utility function with $\CRRA > 1$.\footnote{The main
results also hold for logarithmic utility which is the limit as
$\CRRA \rightarrow 1$ but incorporating the logarithmic special case
in the proofs is cumbersome and therefore
omitted.}$^{,}$\footnote{We will define the infinite horizon
solution as the limit of the finite horizon problem as the horizon
$T-t$ approaches infinity.} The consumer's initial condition is
defined by market resources $\mLevBF_{t}$ (\cite{deatonLiqConstr}
called this `cash-on-hand') and permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t}$.
In the usual treatment, a dynamic budget constraint (DBC) simultaneously incorporates
all of the elements that determine next period's $\mLevBF$ given this
period's choices; but for the detailed analysis here, it will be useful to
disarticulate the steps so that individual ingredients can be separately examined:
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/DBCparts.tex}
\begin{eqnarray}
\aLevBF_{t} &=&\mLevBF_{t}-\cLevBF_{t} \label{eq:DBCparts} \\
\bLevBF_{t+1} & = & \aLevBF_{t} \Rfree \notag \\
\pLevBF_{t+1} &=&\pLevBF_{t} \underbrace{\PGro\pShk_{t+1}}_{\equiv \PGro_{t+1}} \notag \\
\mLevBF_{t+1} &=& \bLevBF_{t+1} +\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}, \notag
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/DBCparts.tex} where $\aLevBF_{t}$ indicates the consumer's assets at the end of period $t$, which grow by a fixed interest factor $\Rfree =(1+\rfree)$ between periods,\footnote{See \cite{mstCapIncFluct} for interesting new work that considers the case where capital returns are stochastic and liquidity constraints exist. \cite{benhabibWealth} examines implications of capital income risk for the distribution of wealth.} so that $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ is the consumer's financial (`bank') balances before next period's consumption choice;\footnote{Allowing a stochastic interest factor is straightforward but adds little insight. The effects are more interesting for analysis of the invariant distribution (\cite{szeidlInvariant}).} $\mLevBF_{t+1}$ (`market resources' or `money') is the sum of financial wealth $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ and noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}$ (permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}$ multiplied by a mean-one iid transitory income shock factor $\tShkAll_{t+1}$; from the perspective of period $t$, future transitory shocks are assumed to satisfy $\Ex_{t}[{\tShkAll}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n\geq 1$). Permanent noncapital income in period $t+1$ is equal to its previous value, multiplied by a growth factor $\PGro$, modified by a mean-one iid shock $\pShk_{t+1}$, $\Ex_{t}[{\pShk}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n \geq 1$ satisfying $\pShk \in [\ushort{\pShk},\bar{\pShk}]$ for $0 < \ushort{\pShk} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\pShk} < \infty$ where $\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$ is the degenerate case with no permanent shocks.\footnote{It is useful to emphasize that permanent noncapital income as defined here differs from what Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonUnderstandingC} calls permanent income (which is often adopted in the macro literature). Deaton defines permanent income as the amount that a perfect foresight consumer could spend while leaving total (human and nonhuman) wealth constant. Relatedly, we refer to $\mLevBF_{t}$ as `cash-on-hand' or `market resources' rather than as wealth to avoid any confusion for readers accustomed to thinking of the discounted value of future noncapital income as a part of wealth. The `market resources' terminology is motivated by the model's assumption that human wealth cannot be capitalized, an implication of anti-slavery laws.} (Hereafter for brevity we occasionally drop time subscripts, e.g.\ $\Ex[\pShk^{-\CRRA}]$ signifies $\Ex_{t}[\pShk_{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]$.)
In future periods $t+n ~\forall~ n \geq 1$ there is a small probability $\pZero$ that income will
be zero (a `zero-income event'),
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/tShkDef}
\begin{equation}
\tShkAll _{t+n}=
\begin{cases}
0\phantom{_{t+1}/\pNotZero} & \text{with probability $\pZero>0$} \\
\tShkEmp_{t+n}/\pNotZero & \text{with probability $\pNotZero $}
\end{cases} \label{eq:tShkDef}
\end{equation}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/tShkDef.tex}
where $\tShkEmp_{t+n}$ is an iid mean-one random variable
($\Ex_{t}[{\tShkEmp}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n>0$)
that has a distribution
satisfying $\tShkEmp \in \lbrack \ushort{\tShkEmp},\bar{\tShkEmp}\rbrack$
where $0<\ushort{\tShkEmp} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\tShkEmp}<\infty$
(degenerately $\ushort{\tShkEmp}=\bar{\tShkEmp}=1$). (See \cite{rabaultBorrowing} and \cite{lsIncFluct} for analyses of cases where the shock processes have unbounded support). Call the cumulative
distribution functions $\CDF_{\pShk}$ and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$ (and $\CDF_{\tShkAll}$
is derived trivially from \eqref{eq:tShkDef} and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$).
Permanent income and cash start out strictly positive, $\{\pLevBF_{t},\mLevBF_{t}\} \in
(0,\infty)$, and as usual the consumer cannot die in
debt, so that
\begin{eqnarray}
\cLevBF_{T} & \leq & \mLevBF_{T} \label{eq:NoDebtAtDeath}.
\end{eqnarray}
The model looks more special than it is. In particular, the
assumption of a positive probability of zero-income events may seem
objectionable. However, it is easy to show that a model with a
nonzero minimum value of $\tShkAll$ (motivated, for example, by the
existence of unemployment insurance) can be redefined by capitalizing
the PDV of minimum income into current market assets,\footnote{So long
as this PDV is a finite number and unemployment benefits are
proportional to $\pLevBF_{t}$; see the discussion in
section~\ref{sec:discussConvergence}.} analytically transforming
that model back into the model analyzed here. Also, the assumption of
a positive point mass (as opposed to positive density) for the worst
realization of the transitory shock is inessential, but simplifies the proofs and is a powerful aid to intuition.
\begin{comment}
Combining the transition equations, the recursive nature of
the problem allows us to rewrite it more compactly in Bellman equation form,
\begin{eqnarray*}
\VFunc_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = & \max_{\cLevBF_{t}}~\left\{\uFunc(\cLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \Ex_{t}\left[ \VFunc_{t+1}((\mLevBF_{t}-\cLevBF_{t})\Rfree+ \pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1},\pLevBF_{t} \PGro \pShk_{t+1})\right]\right\}
.
\end{eqnarray*}
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{DiffWithLit}{} This model differs from Bewley's~\citeyearpar{bewleyPIH} classic formulation in several ways. The CRRA utility function does not satisfy Bewley's assumption that $\uFunc(0)$ is well defined, or that $\uP(0)$ is well defined and finite, so neither the value function nor the marginal value function will be bounded. It differs from Schectman and Escudero~\citeyearpar{seIncFluct} in that they impose liquidity constraints and positive minimum income. It differs from both of these in that it permits permanent growth in income, and also permanent shocks to income, which a large empirical literature finds are quantitatively important in micro data\footnote{MaCurdy~\citeyearpar{macurdyTimeseries}; Abowd and Card~\citeyearpar{acCovariance}; Carroll and Samwick~\citeyearpar{csNature}; Jappelli and Pistaferri~\citeyearpar{jpCins}; Storesletten, Telmer, and Yaron~\citeyearpar{styConsumption}; \cite{blpRisk}} and which since~\cite{friedmanATheory} have been understood to be far more consequential for household welfare than are transitory fluctuations. It differs from Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr} because liquidity constraints are absent; there are separate transitory and permanent shocks ({\it a la} \cite{muthOptimal}); and the transitory shocks here can occasionally cause income to reach zero.\footnote{Below it will become clear that the Deaton model is a particular limit of this paper's model.} Finally, it differs from models found in Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods} because neither liquidity constraints nor bounds on utility or marginal utility are imposed.\footnote{Similar restrictions to those in the cited literature are made in the well known papers by Scheinkman and Weiss~\citeyearpar{scheinkman&weiss:borrowing} and Clarida~\citeyearpar{claridaErgodic}. See \cite{tocheUrisk} for an elegant analysis of a related but simpler continuous-time model.} \cite{asHomogeneous} relaxed the bounds on the return function, but they address only the deterministic case.
The incorporation of permanent shocks rules out application of the tools of \cite{mnUnique}, who followed and corrected an error in the fundamental work on the local contraction mapping method developed in \cite{rrExistence}. \cite{mvExistence} provides another correction to \cite{rrExistence}, and provides conditions that are easier to verify than those of \cite{mvExistence} in many applications, but again only addresses the deterministic case.
\hypertarget{The-Problem-Can-Be-Rewritten-in-Ratio-Form}{}
\subsection{The Problem Can Be Rewritten in Ratio Form}
\label{subsec:ratio}
We establish a bit more notation by reviewing the standard result that in problems of this class (CRRA utility, permanent shocks) the number of relevant state variables can be reduced from two ($\mLevBF$ and $\pLevBF$) to one $(\mRat = \mLevBF/\pLevBF)$. Defining nonbold variables as the boldface counterpart normalized by $\pLevBF_{t}$ (as with $\mRat$ just above), assume that value in the last period of life is $\uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})$, and consider the problem in the second-to-last period,
\begin{eqnarray}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) &=&
\max_{\cLevBF_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(\cLevBF_{T-1}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})]
\notag \\
& = & \max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~
\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T-1}\cRat_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T}{\mRat}
_{T})] \notag \\
& = & \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA}
\left\{\max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(c_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc( {\PGro}_{T}
{\mRat}_{T}) ] \right\} . \label{eq:vBold}
\end{eqnarray}
\hypertarget{The-Related-Problem}{}
Now, in a one-time notational deviation, define nonbold `normalized value' as $\vFunc_{t} = \vLevBF_{t}/\pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}$, and consider the related problem
\begin{eqnarray}
\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}) & = & \max_{\{\cFunc\}_{t}^{T}}~ \uFunc(\cFunc_{t}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t+1}({\mRat}_{t+1})] \notag \\
& \mbox{s.t.} & \label{eq:veqn} \notag
\\ {\aRat}_{t} & = & \mRat_{t}-c_{t} \notag
\\ {\bRat}_{t+1} & = & (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})\aRat_{t} ~ = ~ \Rnorm_{t+1}\aRat_{t} \notag
\\ \mRat_{t+1} & = & \bRat_{t+1}+\tShkAll_{t+1} \notag %
\end{eqnarray}
where $\Rnorm_{t+1}\equiv (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})$ is a `growth-normalized' return factor, and the problem's first order condition is
\begin{eqnarray}
c_{t}^{-\CRRA} & = & \Rfree \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[ {\PGro}_{t+1}^{-\CRRA} {\cRat}
_{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]. \label{eq:scaledeuler}
\end{eqnarray}
Since $\vFunc_{T}(\mRat_{T}) = \uFunc(\mRat_{T})$, defining $\vFunc_{T-1}(\mRat_{T-1})$ from \eqref{eq:veqn} for $t=T-1$, \eqref{eq:vBold} reduces to
\begin{eqnarray*}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) & = & \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA} \vFunc_{T-1}(\underbrace{\mLevBF_{T-1}/\pLevBF_{T-1}}_{=\mRat_{T-1}}).
\end{eqnarray*}
This logic induces to all earlier periods, so that if we solve the
normalized one-state-variable problem specified in \eqref{eq:veqn} we
will have solutions to the original problem for any $t<T$
from:
\begin{eqnarray*}
\vLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = & \pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}),
\\ \cLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = & \pLevBF_{t}\cFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}).
\end{eqnarray*}
\hypertarget{Definition-of-a-Nondegenerate-Solution}{}
\subsection{Definition of a Nondegenerate Solution}
We say that this problem has a nondegenerate solution if it
defines a unique limiting consumption function whose optimal
$\cRat$ satisfies
\begin{eqnarray}
0 & < \cRat < & \infty
\end{eqnarray}
for every $0 < \mRat < \infty.$ (`Degenerate' limits will be cases
where the limiting consumption function is either $\cFunc(\mRat)=0$ or $\cFunc(\mRat)=\infty$.)
\hypertarget{Perfect-Foresight-Benchmarks}{}
\subsection{Perfect Foresight Benchmarks}
Articulating the well-known analytical solution to the perfect foresight specialization of the model, obtained by setting $\pZero=0$ and $\ushort{\tShkEmp}=\bar{\tShkEmp}=\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$, allows us to define some remaining notation and terminology, and to define a convenient reference point.
\hypertarget{Human-Wealth}{}
\subsubsection{Human Wealth}
The dynamic budget constraint, strictly positive marginal utility, and the can't-die-in-debt condition \eqref{eq:NoDebtAtDeath} imply an exactly-holding intertemporal budget constraint (IBC)
\begin{eqnarray}
\text{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = & \overbrace{\mLevBF_{t}-\pLevBF_{t}}^{\bLevBF_{t}}+\overbrace{\text{PDV}_{t}(\pLevBF)}^{\hLevBF_{t}}, \label{eq:IBCFinite}
\end{eqnarray}
where $\bLevBF$ is nonhuman wealth and $\hLevBF_{t}$ is `human wealth,' and with a constant $\Rnorm \equiv \Rfree/\PGro$,
\begin{eqnarray}
\hLevBF_{t} & = & \pLevBF_{t}+\Rnorm^{-1} \pLevBF_{t} + \Rnorm^{-2} \pLevBF_{t} + ... + \Rnorm^{t-T} \pLevBF_{t} \notag
\\ & = & \underbrace{\left(\frac{1-\Rnorm^{-(T-t+1)}}{1-\Rnorm^{-1}}\right)}_{\equiv \hRat_{t}}\pLevBF_{t} \label{eq:HDef}
\end{eqnarray}
Equation \eqref{eq:HDef} makes plain that in order for $\hRat \equiv \lim_{n \rightarrow
\infty} \hRat_{T-n}$ to be finite, we must
impose the Finite Human Wealth Condition (`FHWC') \hypertarget{FHWC}{}
\begin{eqnarray}
\underbrace{\PGro/\Rfree}_{\equiv \Rnorm^{-1}} & < & 1 \label{eq:FHWC}.
\end{eqnarray}
Intuitively, for human wealth to be finite, the growth rate of (noncapital) income must be smaller than
the interest rate at which that income is being discounted.
\hypertarget{Unconstrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{Unconstrained Solution} \label{subsec:PFUncon}
\hypertarget{AIC}{}
The consumption Euler equation holds in every period; with $\uP(\cLevBF)=\cLevBF^{-\CRRA}$, this says
\begin{eqnarray}
\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t} & = & (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} \equiv \Pat \label{eq:cGrowPF} \label{eq:Pat}
\end{eqnarray}
where the Old English letter `thorn' represents what we will call the
`absolute patience factor' $(\Rfree
\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}$.\footnote{Impatience conditions of one kind or
another have figured in intertemporal optimization problems since
such problems were first formalized in economics, most notably by \cite{ramseySave}.
Discussion of these issues was prominent in the literature of the
1960s and 1970s, and no brief citations here could do justice to the literature on the topic, so I refrain from the attempt.} The sense in which $\Pat$ captures
patience is that if the `absolute impatience condition' (AIC) holds,
\begin{eqnarray}
\label{eq:AIC}
\Pat & < & 1,
\end{eqnarray}
the consumer will choose to spend an amount too large to sustain indefinitely (the
level of consumption must fall over time). We say that such a consumer is
`absolutely impatient' (this is the key condition in \cite{bewleyPIH}).
We next define a `return patience factor' that relates absolute patience to the return factor:
\begin{eqnarray}
\PatR & \equiv & {\Pat}/\Rfree \label{eq:PatR}
\end{eqnarray}
and note that since consumption is growing by $\Pat$ but discounted by $\Rfree$:
\begin{eqnarray*}
\text{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = & \left(1+\PatR+\PatR^{2}+...+ \PatR^{T-t}\right)\cLevBF_{t} \notag
\\ & = & \left(\frac{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}{1-\PatR}\right)\cLevBF_{t}
\end{eqnarray*}
from which the IBC \eqref{eq:IBCFinite} implies
\begin{eqnarray}
\cLevBF_{t} & = & \overbrace{\left(\frac{1-\PatR}{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}\right)}^{\equiv \MinMPC_{t}}
(\bLevBF_{t}+\hLevBF_{t}) \label{eq:vecMuDef} \label{eq:WDef}
\end{eqnarray}
which defines a normalized finite-horizon perfect foresight consumption function
\begin{eqnarray}
\bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat_{T-n}) & = & (\overbrace{\mRat_{T-n}-1}^{=\bRat_{T-n}}+\hRat_{T-n})\MinMPC_{T-n}
\end{eqnarray}
where $\MinMPC_{t}$ is the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) because it answers the
question `if the consumer had an extra unit of wealth, how much more would he spend.'
(The overbar on $\cFunc$ reflects the fact that this will be an upper bound as we modify the problem to incorporate constraints and uncertainty; analogously, the underbar for $\MPC$ indicates that it is a lower bound).
Equation \eqref{eq:WDef} makes plain that for the limiting
MPC to be strictly positive as $n=T-t$ goes to infinity we must impose the
condition \hypertarget{RIC}{}
\begin{eqnarray}
\PatR & < & 1 \label{eq:PDVCFinite} \label{eq:RIC},
\end{eqnarray}
so that
\begin{eqnarray}
0 < \MinMPC & \equiv & 1-\PatR = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \MinMPC_{T-n} \label{eq:MinMPCDef}
.
\end{eqnarray}
Equation \eqref{eq:RIC} thus imposes a second kind of `impatience:' The consumer cannot be so pathologically patient as to wish, in the limit as the horizon approaches infinity, to spend nothing today out of an increase in current wealth; that is, the condition rules out the degenerate limiting solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$. Because the return patience factor $\PatR$ is the absolute patience factor divided by the return, we call equation \eqref{eq:RIC} the `return impatience condition' or RIC; we will say that a consumer who satisfies the condition is `return impatient.'
Given that the RIC holds, and defining limiting objects by the absence of a time subscript (e.g., $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\lim_{n \uparrow \infty} \bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat)$), the limiting consumption function will be
\begin{eqnarray}
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & = & (\mRat+\hRat-1)\MinMPC, \label{eq:cFuncPFUnc}
\end{eqnarray}
and we now see that in order to rule out the degenerate limiting
solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) = \infty$ we need $\hRat$ to be finite so we
must impose the finite human wealth condition \eqref{eq:FHWC}.
\hypertarget{ValuePFAnalytical}{}
A final useful point is that since the perfect foresight
growth factor for consumption is $\Pat$, using $\uFunc(xy) =
x^{1-\CRRA}\uFunc(y)$ yields an analytical expression for value:
\begin{eqnarray}
\vRat_{t} & = & \uFunc(\cRat_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\cRat_{t}\Pat)+\DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(\cRat_{t} \Pat^{2})+... \label{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}
\\ & = & \uFunc(\cRat_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
\\ & = & \uFunc(\cRat_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA})^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA}}\right)
\end{eqnarray}
which asymptotes to a finite value as $n=T-t$ approaches $+\infty$ if $\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA} < 1$ (related to a condition in \cite{asHomogeneous}); with a bit of algebra, this requirement can be shown to be equivalent to the RIC.\footnote{
\begin{eqnarray*}
\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA} & < & 1
\\ \DiscFac (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree\DiscFac & < & 1
\\ (\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} /\Rfree & < & 1
\end{eqnarray*}.
} Thus, the same conditions that guarantee a nondegenerate limiting consumption function also guarantee a nondegenerate limiting value function (this will not be true in the version of the model that incorporates uncertainty).
\hypertarget{Constrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{Constrained Solution}
If a liquidity constraint requiring $\bRat \geq 0$ is ever to be relevant, it must be
relevant at the lowest possible level of market resources,
$\mRat_{t}=1$, which obtains for a consumer who enters period $t$ with
$\bRat_{t}=0$. The constraint is `relevant' if
it prevents the choice that would otherwise be optimal; at
$\mRat_{t}=1$ the constraint is relevant if the marginal utility from spending all of today's
resources $c_{t}=m_{t}=1$, exceeds the marginal utility from
doing the same thing next period, $\cRat_{t+1}=1$; that is, if such
choices would violate the Euler equation \eqref{eq:scaledeuler}:
\begin{eqnarray}
1^{-\CRRA} & > & \Rfree \DiscFac (\PGro)^{-\CRRA}1^{-\CRRA} \label{eq:LiqConstrBinds}.
\end{eqnarray}
\hypertarget{PFGIC}{}
By analogy to the return patience factor, we therefore define a `perfect
foresight growth patience factor' as
\begin{eqnarray}
\PatPGro & = & {\Pat}/\PGro, \label{eq:PFGPF}
\end{eqnarray}
and define a `perfect foresight growth impatience condition' (PF-GIC)
\begin{eqnarray}
\label{eq:PFGIC}
\PatPGro & < & 1
\end{eqnarray}
which is equivalent to \eqref{eq:LiqConstrBinds} (exponentiate both
sides by $1/\CRRA$).
If the RIC and the FHWC hold, appendix \ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows
that, for some $0 < \mRat_{\#} < 1$, an unconstrained consumer behaving according to
\eqref{eq:cFuncPFUnc} would choose $\cRat < \mRat$ for all $\mRat >
\mRat_{\#}$. The solution to the
constrained consumer's problem in this case is simple: For any $\mRat
\geq \mRat_{\#}$ the constraint does not bind (and will never bind in
the future) and so the constrained consumption function is identical
to the unconstrained one. In principle, if the consumer were somehow\footnote{``Somehow'' because such values
of $\mRat$ are of questionable relevance: They could only be
obtained by entering the period with $\bRat < 0$ which the constraint
rules out).}
to arrive at an $\mRat < \mRat_{\#} < 1$ the constraint would bind and
the consumer would have to consume $\cRat=\mRat$. We use the $\circ$ accent to designate the limiting
constrained consumption function:
\begin{equation}
\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)=
\begin{cases}
\mRat & \text{if $\mRat < \mRat_{\#}$} \\
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & \text{if $\mRat \geq \mRat_{\#}$.}
\end{cases}
\end{equation}
More useful is the case where the perfect foresight growth and return impatience conditions both hold. In this case appendix \ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows that the limiting constrained consumption function is piecewise linear, with $\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\mRat$ up to a first `kink point' at $\mRat_{\#}^{1}>1$, and with discrete declines in the MPC at successively increasing kink points $\{\mRat_{\#}^{1},\mRat_{\#}^{2},...\}$. As $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the constrained consumption function $\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ becomes arbitrarily close to the unconstrained $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)$, and the marginal propensity to consume function $\mathring{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) \equiv \mathring{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat)$ limits to $\MinMPC$. Similarly, the value function $\mathring{\vFunc}(\mRat)$ is nondegenerate and limits into the value function of the unconstrained consumer. Surprisingly, this logic holds even when the finite human wealth condition fails (denoted \cancel{FHWC}). A solution exists because the constraint prevents the consumer from borrowing against infinite human wealth to finance infinite current consumption. Under these circumstances, the consumer who starts with any amount of resources $\bRat_{t} > 1$ will run those resources down over time so that by some finite number of periods $n$ in the future the consumer will reach $\bRat_{t+n} = 0$, and thereafter will set $\cRat = \mRat = 1$ for eternity, a policy that will (using \eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}) yield value of \hypertarget{PFFVAC}{}
\begin{eqnarray}
\vLevBF_{t+n} & = & \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t+n})\left(1+\DiscFac
\PGro^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right) \notag
\\ & = & \PGro^{n(1-\CRRA)} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac
\PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{T-(t+n)+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}}\right),
\notag
\end{eqnarray}
which will be finite whenever
\begin{eqnarray}
\overbrace{\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAlt} & < & 1 \label{eq:PFFVAC}
\\ \DiscFac \Rfree \PGro^{-\CRRA} & < & \Rfree/\PGro \nonumber
\\ \PatPGro & < & (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA} \label{eq:PFFVACv2}
\end{eqnarray}
which we call the Perfect Foresight Finite Value of Autarky Condition, PF-FVAC, because it guarantees that a consumer who always spends all his permanent income will have finite value (the consumer has `finite autarky value'). Note that the version of the PF-FVAC in \eqref{eq:PFFVACv2} implies the PF-GIC $\PatPGro < 1$ whenever \cancel{FHWC} $\Rfree < \PGro$ holds. So, if \cancel{FHWC}, value for any finite $\mRat$ will be the sum of two finite numbers: The component due to the unconstrained consumption choice made over the finite horizon leading up to $\bRat_{t+n} = 0$, and the finite component due to the value of consuming all income thereafter. The consumer's value function is therefore nondegenerate.
The most peculiar possibility occurs when the RIC fails. The appendix shows that under these circumstances the FHWC
must also fail, and the constrained consumption function is nondegenerate. (See Figure~\ref{fig:PFGICHoldsFHWCFailsRICFails} for a numerical example). While it is true that $\lim_{m \uparrow \infty}
\mathring{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) = 0$, nevertheless the limiting constrained
consumption function $\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ is strictly positive
and strictly increasing in $\mRat$. This result interestingly
reconciles the conflicting intuitions from the unconstrained case,
where \cancel{RIC} would suggest a dengenerate limit of
$\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ while \cancel{FHWC} would suggest a
degenerate limit of $\mathring{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$.
Tables~\ref{table:Comparison} and \ref{table:Required} (and appendix
table~\ref{table:LiqConstrScenarios}) codify the key points to help
the reader keep them straight (and to facilitate upcoming comparisons
with the results in the presence of uncertainty
but the absence of liquidity constraints (also tabulated for comparison)). The model without constraints but with uncertainty will turn out to be a close parallel to the model with constraints but without uncertainty.
\hypertarget{Uncertainty-Modified-Conditions}{}
\subsection{Uncertainty-Modified Conditions}
\subsubsection{Impatience}
When uncertainty is introduced, the expectation of $\bRat_{t+1}$ can be rewritten as:
\begin{eqnarray}
\Ex_{t}[\bRat_{t+1}] & = & \aRat_{t}\Ex_{t}[\Rnorm_{t+1}] = \aRat_{t}\Rnorm\Ex_{t}[\pShk_{t+1}^{-1}] \label{eq:EbRat}
\end{eqnarray}
where Jensen's inequality guarantees that the expectation of the inverse of the permanent
shock is strictly greater than one. It will be convenient to define the object
\begin{eqnarray*}
\InvEpShkInv & \equiv & (\EpShkInv)^{-1}
\end{eqnarray*}
because this permits us to write expressions like the RHS of
\eqref{eq:EbRat} compactly as, e.g., $\aRat_{t}\Rnorm
\InvEpShkInv^{-1}.$\footnote{One way to think of $\InvEpShkInv$ is as
a particular kind of a `certainty equivalent' of the shock; this
captures the intuition that mean-one shock renders a given mean
level of income less valuable than if the shock did not exist, so
that $\InvEpShkInv < 1$.} We refer to this as the `compensated return,' because it compensates (in a risk-neutral way) for the effect of
uncertainty on the expected growth-normalized return (in the sense implicitly defined in
\eqref{eq:EbRat}). Note that Jensen's inequality implies that $\InvEpShkInv < 1$ for nondegenerate $\psi$ (since
$\Ex[\psi]=1$ by assumption).
\hypertarget{GIC}{}
We can now transparently generalize the PF-GIC \eqref{eq:PFGIC} by defining a `compensated growth factor'
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PGroAdj}
\begin{eqnarray}
\PGroAdj & = & \PGro \InvEpShkInv \label{eq:PGroAdj}
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/PGroAdj}
and a compensated growth patience factor\hypertarget{GIF}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
\begin{eqnarray}
\PatPGroAdj & = & \Pat/\PGroAdj
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
and a straightforward derivation
using some of the results below yields the conclusion that
\begin{eqnarray*}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \rightarrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[\mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_{t}] & = & \PatPGroAdj,
\end{eqnarray*}
which implies that if we wish to prevent $\mRat$ from heading to infinity (that is, if we want $m$ to be guaranteed to be expected to fall for some large enough value of $m$) we must impose a generalized version of the Perfect Foresight Growth Impatience Conditon \eqref{eq:PFGIC} which we call simply the `growth impatience condition'
(GIC):\footnote{Equation \eqref{eq:GIC} is a bit easier to satisfy than the similar condition imposed by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}: $\left(\Ex[\pShk^{-\CRRA}]\right)^{1/\CRRA} \PatPGro < 1$ to guarantee that his problem defined a contraction mapping.}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/GIC}
\begin{eqnarray}
\PatPGroAdj & < & 1 \label{eq:GIC}
\end{eqnarray}\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/GIC}
which is stronger than the perfect foresight version \eqref{eq:PFGIC} because $\PGroAdj < \PGro$.
\hypertarget{Autarky-Value}{}
\subsubsection{Autarky Value}
Analogously to \eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}, a consumer who spent his permanent income every period would have value
\begin{eqnarray*}
\vLevBF_{t} & = & \Ex_{t}\left[\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}) + \DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}) + ... + \DiscFac^{T-t}\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}...\PGro_{T})\right] \\
& = & \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+ \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}] + ... + \DiscFac^{T-t}\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}]...\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{T}^{1-\CRRA}]\right) \\
& = & \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} \Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}]}\right)
\end{eqnarray*}
which invites the definition of a utility-compensated equivalent of the permanent shock,
\begin{eqnarray*}
\uInvEpShkuInv & = & (\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])^{1/(1-\CRRA)}
\end{eqnarray*}
which will satisfy $\uInvEpShkuInv < 1$ for $\CRRA>1$ and nondegenerate $\pShk$ (and $\uInvEpShkuInv < \InvEpShkInv$ for the preferred (though not required) case of $\CRRA > 2$); defining $\PGrouAdj=\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv$ we can see that $\vLevBF_{t}$ will be finite as $T$ approaches $\infty$ if
\hypertarget{FVAC}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/FVAC}
\begin{eqnarray}
\overbrace{\DiscFac \PGrouAdj^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAltuAdj} & < & 1 \label{eq:FVAC}
\\ \DiscFac & < & \PGrouAdj^{\CRRA-1} \notag
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/FVAC} which we call the `finite value of autarky'
condition (FVAC) because it is the value obtained by always consuming
permanent income. For nondegenerate $\pShk$, this condition is stronger
(harder to satisfy in the sense of requiring lower $\DiscFac$) than
the perfect foresight version \eqref{eq:PFFVAC} because $\PGrouAdj <
\PGro$.
\begin{comment}
A useful alternative version is
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/FVACAlt}
\begin{eqnarray}
\DiscFac \Rfree \PGro^{-\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA} & < & \Rfree/\PGro \nonumber
\\ \PatPGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{1/\CRRA-1} & < & (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA} \label{eq:FVACAlt}.
\end{eqnarray}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/FVACAlt}
\end{comment}
\begin{comment}
In the case where the permanent shocks are lognormally distributed, we have
\begin{eqnarray}
\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] & = &\exp((1-\CRRA)(-\sigma^{2}_{\pshk}/2)+(1-\CRRA)^{2}\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\\ & = & \exp((1-\CRRA)((-1/2)+(1-\CRRA))\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\\ & = & \exp((1-\CRRA)(1/2-\CRRA)\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\end{eqnarray}
\end{comment}
\begin{comment}
Equation
\eqref{eq:GIC} can be raised to the $\CRRA$ power yielding the
alternative form $(\Rfree \DiscFac) \PGroAdj^{-\CRRA} < 1$ which
Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr} imposed to guarantee that his
problem defined a contraction mapping.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Baseline-Numerical-Solution}{}
\subsection{The Baseline Numerical Solution}
Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge} depicts the successive consumption
rules that apply in the last period of life ($\cFunc_{T}(\mRat)$), the
second-to-last period, and various earlier periods under the
baseline parameter values listed in Table~\ref{table:Calibration}.
(The 45 degree line is labelled as $\cFunc_{T}(\mRat) = m$ because in
the last period of life it is optimal to spend all remaining
resources.)
\input{\TableDir/Calibration.tex}
\providecommand{\figName}{Convergence-of-the-Consumption-Rules}
\providecommand{\figFile}{cFuncsConverge}
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\begin{figure}[tbp]
\centerline{\includegraphics[width=6in]{\FigDir/\figFile}}
\caption{Convergence of the Consumption Rules}
\label{fig:\figFile}
\end{figure}
In the figure, the consumption rules appear to converge as the horizon
recedes (our purpose is to show that this appearance is not deceptive); we
call the limiting infinite-horizon consumption rule
\begin{eqnarray}
\cFunc(\mRat) & \equiv & \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}(\mRat).
\end{eqnarray}
\hypertarget{Concave-Consumption-Function-Characteristics}{}
\subsection{Concave Consumption Function Characteristics}\label{sec:cExists}
A precondition for the main proof is that the maximization problem \eqref{eq:veqn} defines a sequence of continuously differentiable strictly increasing strictly concave\footnote{There is one obvious exception: $\cFunc_{T}(m)$ is a linear (and so only weakly concave) function.} functions $\{\cFunc_{T},\cFunc_{T-1},...\}$.\footnote{\cite{ckConcavity} proved concavity but not the other desired properties.} The straightforward but tedious proof of this precondition is relegated to appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxcExists}. For present purposes, the most important point is the following intuition: $\cFunc_{t}(\mRat) < m$ for all periods $t < T$ because a consumer who spent all available resources would arrive in period $t+1$ with balances $b_{t+1}$ of zero, and then might earn zero noncapital income over the remaining horizon (an unbroken series of zero-income events is unlikely but possible). In such a case, the budget constraint and the can't-die-in-debt condition mean that the consumer would be forced to spend zero, incurring negative infinite utility. To avoid this disaster, the consumer never spends everything. (This is an example of the `natural borrowing constraint' induced by a precautionary motive (\cite{zeldesStochastic}).)\footnote{It would perhaps be better to call it the `utility-induced borrowing constraint' as it follows from the assumptions on the utility function (in particular, $\lim_{c \downarrow 0} \uFunc(c)=-\infty$); for example, no such constraint arises if utility is of the (implausible) Constant Absolute Risk Aversion form.}
\hypertarget{Bounds-for-the-Consumption-Functions}{}
\subsection{Bounds for the Consumption Functions}
The consumption functions depicted in Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge} appear
to have limiting slopes as $\mRat \downarrow 0$ and as $\mRat \uparrow
\infty$. This section confirms that impression and derives those
slopes, which also turn out to be useful in the contraction
mapping proof. In a recent paper, \cite{benhabibWealth} show that the consumption function
becomes linear as wealth approaches infinity in a model with capital income risk and liquidity
constraints; it seems clear that their results would generalize to the limits derived here if capital income risk were added to the model. See also \cite{mstCapIncFluct} for an analysis of the stability of models with capital income risk.
\newcommand{\NewMaxMinMPC}{\ushort{\MPC}}
Assume (as discussed above) that a continuously differentiable
concave consumption function exists in period $t+1$, with an origin at
$\cFunc_{t+1}(0)=0$, a minimal MPC $\NewMaxMinMPC_{t+1}>0$, and
maximal MPC $\MaxMPC_{t+1} \leq 1$. (If $t+1 = T$ these will be
$\NewMaxMinMPC_{T}=\MaxMPC_{T}=1$; for earlier periods they will exist
by recursion from the following arguments.)
The MPC bound as wealth approaches infinity is easy to understand: In this case,
under our imposed assumption about finite human wealth, the proportion of consumption
that will be financed out of human wealth approaches zero. The
consequence is that the proportional difference between the solution to the
model with uncertainty and the perfect foresight model shrinks to zero.
\hypertarget{MPCnvrsLower}{}
In the course of proving this point, appendix~\ref{sec:MPCLimits} provides a useful recursive expression for the (inverse of the) limiting MPC:
\begin{eqnarray}
\MinMPC_{t}^{-1} & = & 1+\MaxMPS \MinMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MinMPCInv}.
\end{eqnarray}
\hypertarget{MPCnvrsUpper}{}
\hypertarget{WRIC}{}
It turns out that there is a parallel expression for the limiting maximal
MPC as $\mRat \downarrow 0$: appendix equation \eqref{eq:MaxMPCInv} shows that, as $\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty$,
\begin{eqnarray}
\MaxMPC_{t}^{-1} & = & 1+\MinMPS \MaxMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MaxMPCInv}.
\end{eqnarray}
Then
$\left\{\MaxMPC_{T-n}^{-1}\right\} _{n=0}^{\infty}$ is a decreasing
convergent sequence if
\begin{eqnarray}
0 \leq & \pZero^{1/\CRRA} \PatR & < 1 \label{eq:WRIC},
\end{eqnarray}
a condition that we dub the `Weak Return Impatience Condition' (WRIC)
because with $\pZero < 1$ it will hold more easily (for a larger set of parameter
values) than the RIC ($\PatR < 1$).
The essence of the argument is that as wealth approaches zero, the overriding
consideration that limits consumption is the (recursive) fear of the zero
income events. (That consideration is the reason the probability of the zero
income event $\pZero$ appears in the expression.)
We are now in position to observe that the optimal consumption function must satisfy
\begin{eqnarray}
\MinMinMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} ~ \leq & \cFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}) & \leq ~ \MaxMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} \label{eq:cBounds}
\end{eqnarray}
because consumption starts at zero and is continuously
differentiable (as argued above), is strictly
concave (\cite{ckConcavity}), and always exhibits a
slope between $\MinMinMPC_{t}$ and $\MaxMPC_{t}$ (the formal proof is provided in appendix \ref{sec:Tcomplete}).
These limits are useful at least in the sense that they can be hard-wired into a solution algorithm for the model, which has the potential to make the solution more efficient (cf.\ \cite{cctwMoM}). Alternatively, they can provide a useful check on the accuracy of a solution algorithm that does not impose them directly.
\begin{comment}
If the FHWC does not hold, we make do with a less useful bound on the minimal MPC: It is
weakly greater than zero, which follows from the logic in
\ref{sec:cExists}; hence the `max' in \eqref{eq:MinMinMPCDef}.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Conditions-Under-Which-the-Problem-Defines-a-Contraction-Mapping}{}
\subsection{Conditions Under Which the Problem Defines a Contraction Mapping}
\label{subsec:contraction}
To prove that the consumption rules converge, we need to show that the
problem defines a contraction mapping. This cannot be proven using the
standard theorems in, say, Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods},
which require marginal utility to be bounded over the space of
possible values of $\mRat$, because the possibility (however unlikely)
of an unbroken string of zero-income events for the remainder of life
means that as $\mRat$ approaches zero $c$ must approach zero (see the
discussion in \ref{sec:cExists}); thus, marginal utility is unbounded.
Although a recent literature examines the existence and uniqueness
of solutions to Bellman equations in the presence of `unbounded returns' (see, e.g.,
\cite{mnUnique}), the techniques in that literature
cannot be used to solve the problem here because the required conditions
are violated by a problem that involves permanent shocks.\footnote{See \cite{yaoNote}
for a detailed discussion of the reasons the existing literature up through \cite{mnUnique} cannot handle
the problem described here.}
Fortunately, Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} provided a weighted contraction mapping theorem that \cite{asHomogeneous} showed how to use to to address the homogeneous case (of which CRRA formulation is an example) in a deterministic framework, and \cite{duranDiscounting} showed how to extend \cite{jboydWeighted} approach to the stochastic case.
\begin{defn}
Consider any function $\bullet\in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ where $\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ is the space of continuous functions from $\mathscr{A}$ to $%
\mathscr{B}$. Suppose $\phiFunc \in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ with $%
\mathscr{B}\subseteq\mathbb{R}$ and $\phiFunc >0$. Then $\bullet$ is $\phiFunc$-bounded if the $\phiFunc$-norm of $\bullet$,
\begin{equation}
\Vert \bullet\Vert _{\phiFunc }=\sup_{\mRat}\left[ \frac{|\bullet(\mRat)|}{\phiFunc (\mRat)}\right] ,
\label{eq:phinorm}
\end{equation}%
is finite.
\end{defn}
For $\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $
defined as the set of functions in
$\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ that are $\phiFunc$-bounded;
$\wFunc$, $\xFunc$, $\yFunc$, and $\zFunc$ as examples of
$\phiFunc$-bounded functions; and using $\mathbf{0}(\mRat)=0$ to
indicate the function that returns zero for any argument,
Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} proves the following.
\newcommand{\BoydT}{\mathsf{T}}
\newcommand{\Shrinker}{\alpha}
\textbf{Boyd's Weighted Contraction Mapping Theorem.} \textit{Let $\BoydT:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right)
\rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $ such
that}\footnote{We will usually denote the function that results from the mapping as, e.g., $\{\BoydT\wFunc\}$.}$^,$\footnote{To non-theorists, this notation may be slightly confusing; the inequality relations in 1) and 3) are taken to mean `for any specific element $\bullet$ in the domain of the functions in question' so that, e.g., $\xFunc \leq \yFunc$ is short for $\xFunc(\bullet) \leq \yFunc(\bullet)~\forall~\bullet\in \mathscr{A}.$ In this notation, $\zeta \Shrinker \phiFunc$ in 3) is a {\it function} which can be applied to any argument $\bullet$ (because $\phiFunc$ is a function).} \nopagebreak
\begin{eqnarray*}
\mbox{1)} &&\BoydT%
\mbox{ {\it is non-decreasing, i.e.\ ${\xFunc} \leq {\yFunc}\Rightarrow
\{\BoydT{\xFunc}\} \leq \{\BoydT{\yFunc}\}$}} \nonumber \\
\mbox{2)} && \{\BoydT\mathbf{0}\}\in ~ \mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \notag \\
\mbox{3)}
&& \mbox{\it There exists some real $0 < \Shrinker < 1$, such that} \\
&& \{\BoydT({\wFunc} +\zeta\phiFunc )\} \leq \{\BoydT{\wFunc}\} +\zeta\Shrinker \phiFunc
\mbox{ {\it ~holds for all real $\zeta > 0$} }.
\end{eqnarray*}%
\textit{Then $\BoydT$ defines a contraction with a unique fixed point.}
For our problem, take $\mathscr{A}$ as $\mathbb{R}_{++}$ and $\mathscr{B}$
as $\mathbb{R}$, and define
\begin{eqnarray*}
\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t}) & = & \Ex_{t}\left[\PGro^{1-\CRRA}_{t+1} \zFunc(a_{t} \Rnorm_{t+1} + \tShkAll_{t+1})\right].
\end{eqnarray*}
Using this, we introduce the mapping \textit{$\TMap:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left(
\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $},\footnote{Note that the existence of the maximum is assured by the continuity of $\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t})$ (it is continuous because it is the sum of continuous $\phiFunc$-bounded functions $\zFunc$) and the compactness of $[\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]$.}
\begin{comment} %
(In the subtle case when $\MinMinMPC=0$, the compact interval could be revised as $ [(\MinMinMPC+\epsilon) \mRat_{t},
\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]$ where $\epsilon$ is a very small positive number because obviously $\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}=0$ will not be the $\argmax$)
\end{comment}
\begin{eqnarray}
\{\TMap{\zFunc}\}(\mRat_{t}) &=&\underset{{\cRat}_{t} \in
[\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]
} \max
\uFunc(c_{t})+\DiscFac \left( \{\EEndMap \zFunc \}(\mRat_{t}-c_{t}) \right) \label{definitionmappingT}.
\end{eqnarray}
\begin{comment}
Unpacking the definitions, our mapping $\TMap$ can be written more explicitly as
\begin{eqnarray}
\{\TMap\zFunc\}(\mRat_{t}) &=&\underset{\cRat_{t} \in [\MinMinMPC
\mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]} \max \left\{
\uFunc(c_{t})+\DiscFac \Ex_{t}\left[ {\PGro}_{t+1} ^{1-\CRRA }\zFunc(
{\aRat}_{t}\Rnorm_{t+1}+\tShkAll_{t+1}) \right] \right\}
.
\end{eqnarray}
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Contraction-Conditions}{}
We can show that our operator $\TMap$ satisfies the conditions that
Boyd requires of his operator $\BoydT$, if we impose two restrictions
on parameter values. The first restriction is the WRIC necessary for
convergence of the maximal MPC, equation \eqref{eq:WRIC} above. A
more serious restriction is the utility-compensated Finite Value of
Autarky condition, equation \eqref{eq:FVAC}. (We discuss the
interpretation of these restrictions in detail in section
\ref{sec:discussConvergence} below.) Imposing these restrictions, we
are now in position to state the central theorem of the paper.
\setcounter{theorem}{0}
\begin{theorem}
\label{thm:contmap} $\TMap$ is a contraction mapping if
the restrictions on parameter values \eqref{eq:WRIC} and
\eqref{eq:FVAC} are true.
\end{theorem}
The proof is cumbersome, and therefore relegated to
appendix~\ref{sec:Tcomplete}. Given that the value function
converges, appendix~\ref{sec:cConverges} shows that the consumption
functions converge.
\hypertarget{The-Liquidity-Constrained-Solution-as-a-Limit}{}
\subsection{The Liquidity Constrained Solution as a Limit} \label{sec:deatonIsLimit}
This section shows that a related problem commonly considered in the
literature (e.g., with a simpler income process, by
Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}), with a liquidity constraint
and a positive minimum value of income, is the limit of the problem
considered here as the probability $\pZero$ of the zero-income event
approaches zero.
The essence of the argument is easy to state. As noted above, there is a finite possibility of earning zero income over the remainder of the horizon, which prevents
the consumer from ending the current period with zero assets because
with some finite probability the consumer would be forced to consume zero,
which would be infinitely painful.
But \textit{extent} to which the consumer feels the need to make this
precautionary provision depends on the probability that it will turn
out to matter. As $\pZero \downarrow 0$, that probability becomes
arbitrarily small, so the amount of precautionary saving approaches zero.
But zero precautionary saving is the amount of saving that a liquidity
constrained consumer with perfect foresight would choose.
Another way to think about this is just to think of the liquidity
constraint as being imposed by specifying a component of the utility
function that is zero whenever the consumer ends the period with
(weakly) positive assets, but negative infinity if the consumer
ended the period with (strictly) negative assets.
See appendix \ref{sec:LiqConstrAsLimit} for the formal proof justifying the
foregoing intuitive discussion.
\hypertarget{Discussion-of-Parametric-Restrictions}{}
\subsection{Discussion of Parametric Restrictions}\label{sec:discussConvergence}
\begin{comment}
\subsubsection{Perfect Foresight Case}
The unconstrained perfect foresight model is the natural starting
point for developing the intuition behind our parametric restrictions.
As noted above, the Return Impatience Condition (RIC) is necessary in
this context to guarantee that the PDV of the stream of future
consumption is finite; value is then given by
\begin{eqnarray*}
\vLevBF_{t} & = & \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\overbrace{(\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}\cLevBF_{t}}^{=\cLevBF_{t+1}})+\DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{2}\cLevBF_{t})+...
\\ & = & \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
\end{eqnarray*}
which has a finite limit so long as $\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA} < 1$. But
\begin{eqnarray*}
\DiscFac ({\Pat})^{1-\CRRA} & = & \DiscFac (\DiscFac \Rfree)^{1/\CRRA - 1}
\\ & = & {\Pat}/\Rfree = \PatR
\end{eqnarray*}
so the RIC guarantees the finiteness of value in addition to the PDV
of consumption (given a finite starting point).
The starting point for consumption is guaranteed to be finite by
imposition of the finite human wealth (FHWC) requirement. (If human
wealth were unbounded, our unconstrained consumer could freely borrow
in order to spend an infinite amount in every period.)
An alternative way to limit consumption is by imposing a liquidity
constraint $\cRat_{t} \leq \mRat_{t}$. Naturally, in the presence of
such an urgent constraint, other constraints become less important.
Indeed, the strength of the liquidity constraint can be appreciated
from the fact that it prevents consumption from exceeding current
resources even when human wealth is infinite.
Value, in the constrained case, is easy to calculate, because the
constrained consumer's spending is always equal to income, which
always grows by $\PGro$:
\begin{eqnarray}
\vLevBF_{t} & = & \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t} \PGro) + \DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t} \PGro^{2}) ... \notag
\\ & = & \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
\end{eqnarray}
which explains the perfect foresight finite value requirement
\eqref{eq:FVAC}: It guarantees that value for the constrained
consumer is finite. Thus, the introduction of constraints is what
makes the finite value requirement interesting; with finite value it becomes
possible to calculate the consequences of alternatives.
\end{comment}
\subsubsection{The RIC}
In the perfect foresight unconstrained problem
(section~\ref{subsec:PFUncon}), the RIC was required for existence of
a nondegenerate solution. It is surprising, therefore, that in the
presence of uncertainty, the RIC is neither necessary nor sufficient
for a nondegenerate solution.
\begin{comment}
But if the RIC does hold, some useful results can be derived. Arguably
the most fundamental are that the limiting values
for the minimal and maximal marginal propensities to consume implicit in
\eqref{eq:MaxMPCDef} and \eqref{eq:MinMPCInv} are positive and finite.
\end{comment}
We thus begin our discussion by asking what features the problem must
exhibit (given the FVAC) if the RIC fails (that is, $\Rfree < (\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})$:
\begin{eqnarray}
\Rfree & < & \overbrace{(\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} ~ < ~ (\Rfree (\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv)^{\CRRA-1})^{1/\CRRA}}^{\text{implied by FVAC}} \notag
\\ \Rfree & < & (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ \Rfree/\PGro & < & (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1-1/\CRRA} & < & \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \label{eq:RICimplies}
\end{eqnarray}
but since $\uInvEpShkuInv<1$ and $0 < 1-1/\CRRA < 1$ (because we have
assumed $\CRRA > 1$), this can hold only if $\Rfree/\PGro < 1$; that
is, given the FVAC, the RIC can fail only if human wealth is
unbounded. Unbounded human wealth is permitted here, as in the
perfect foresight liquidity constrained problem. But,
from equation
\eqref{eq:MinMPCInv}, an implication of \cancel{RIC} is that $\lim_{m
\uparrow \infty} \cFunc^{\prime}(m) = 0$. Thus, interestingly,
the presence of uncertainty both permits unlimited human wealth and at
the same time prevents that unlimited wealth from resulting in
infinite consumption. That is, in the presence of uncertainty,
pathological patience (which in the perfect foresight model with
finite wealth results in consumption of zero) plus infinite human
wealth (which the perfect foresight model rules out because it leads
to infinite consumption) combine here to yield a unique finite
limiting MPC for any finite value of $\mRat$. Note
the close parallel to the conclusion in the perfect foresight
liquidity constrained model in the
$\{$PF-GIC,\cancel{RIC}$\}$ case (for detailed analysis of this
case see the appendix). There, too, the tension between infinite human wealth
and pathological patience was resolved with a nondegenerate consumption function
whose limiting MPC was zero.
\subsubsection{The WRIC}
The `weakness' of the additional requirement for contraction, the
weak RIC, can be seen by asking `under what circumstances
would the FVAC hold but the WRIC fail?'
Algebraically, the requirement is
\begin{eqnarray}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA} & < ~ 1 ~ < & (\pZero \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree^{1-1/\CRRA}. \label{eq:WRICandFVAC}
\end{eqnarray}
If there were no conceivable parameter values that could satisfy both
of these inequalities, the WRIC would have no force; it would be
redundant. And if we require $\Rfree \geq 1$, the WRIC is indeed
redundant because now $\DiscFac <1<\Rfree^{\CRRA-1}$, so that the RIC (and WRIC) must hold.
But neither theory nor evidence demands that we assume $\Rfree \geq
1$. We can therefore approach the question of the WRIC's relevance by
asking just how low $\Rfree$ must be for the condition to be relevant.
Suppose for illustration that $\CRRA=2$, $\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA}=1.01$,
$\PGro^{1-\CRRA}=1.01^{-1}$ and $\pZero = 0.10$. In that case
\eqref{eq:WRICandFVAC} reduces to
\begin{eqnarray}
\DiscFac & < 1 < & (0.1 \DiscFac/\Rfree)^{1/2} \notag
\end{eqnarray}
but since $\DiscFac < 1$ by assumption, the binding requirement is that
\begin{eqnarray}
\Rfree & < & \DiscFac/10 \notag
\end{eqnarray}
so that for example if $\DiscFac=0.96$ we would need $\Rfree < 0.096$
(that is, a perpetual riskfree rate of return of worse than -90
percent a year) in order for the WRIC to bind.
Thus, the relevance of the WRIC is indeed ``Weak.''
Perhaps the best way of thinking about this is to note that the space
of parameter values for which the WRIC is relevant shrinks out of
existence as $\pZero \rightarrow 0$, which section
\ref{sec:deatonIsLimit} showed was the precise limiting condition
under which behavior becomes arbitrarily close to the liquidity
constrained solution (in the absence of other risks). On the other
hand, when $\pZero = 1$, the consumer has no noncapital income (so
that the FHWC holds) and with $\pZero=1$ the WRIC is identical to the
RIC; but the RIC is
the only condition required for a solution to exist
for a perfect foresight consumer with no noncapital income. Thus the
WRIC forms a sort of `bridge' between the liquidity constrained and
the unconstrained problems as $\pZero$ moves from 0 to 1.
\hypertarget{The-GIC}{}
\hypertarget{When-the-GIC-Fails}{}
\subsubsection{When the GIC Fails}
If both the GIC and the RIC hold, the arguments above establish that the limiting consumption
function asymptotes to the consumption function for the perfect foresight unconstrained function.
The more interesting case is where the GIC fails.
\begin{comment}
\WW{}{The same
steps as above lead to the same implication that this requires
$\InvEpShkInv < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}$,
but when the RIC $\Rfree/\PGro > 1$ holds this condition is much more
easily satisfied.}
If the FVAC holds but the GIC does not, the parameters must satisfy:
\begin{eqnarray}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] & < 1 < & (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}(\PGro\Ex[\pshk^{-1}])^{-1}. \label{eq:FVACnotGIC}
\end{eqnarray}
Note first that by Jensens's inequality $\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] > 1$ and $(\Ex[\pshk^{-1}])^{-1} < 1$,
so \eqref{eq:FVACnotGIC} is stronger than
\begin{eqnarray}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} & < 1 < & (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\PGro. \label{eq:PFFVACnotPFGIC}
\end{eqnarray}
Suppose $\PGro=1$, $\CRRA=2$ and $\pshk$ is lognormally distributed with $\sigma^{2}_{\pshk}=0.01$ (that is, $\log \pshk \sim \mathcal{N}(-\sigma_{\psi}^{2}/2,\sigma_{\psi}^{2})$) so that $\Ex_{t}[\pshk_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}] =\Ex_{t}[\pshk_{t+1}^{-1}] =\exp(\sigma^{2}_{\psi})=e^{0.01}.$ Then the condition becomes
\begin{eqnarray}