-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
grasping.tex
288 lines (179 loc) · 113 KB
/
grasping.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
%!TEX root = /Users/markelikalderon/Documents/Git/sympathy/perception.tex
\chapter{Grasping} % (fold)
\label{cha:grasping}
% \epigraph{``For example\ldots my\ldots hand'' is Husserl's phrase, and so is ``for example, the\ldots finger.'' Sometimes it is \emph{zum Beispiel} that ``for example'' translates (for example, my hand), and sometimes it is \emph{etwa} (approximately as, like, for example\ldots the finger.)\\ Hence, exemplariness.}{Derrida, \emph{Le Toucher---Jean Luc Nancy}}
\section{The Dawn of Understanding} % (fold)
\label{sec:grasping_and_the_dawn_of_understanding}
In a justly famous scene from \emph{2001: A Space Odyssey}, set to Richard Strauss' \emph{Also Sprach Zarathustra}, a hominid ancestor, squatting among the skeletal remains of a tapir, reaches out and tentatively grasps a femur. It is telling that this is how Stanley Kubrick chose to dramatize the initial transformation, induced by an alien obelisk, of our hominid ancestors, that eventually gives rise to space-exploring humanity in the twenty-first century. Not only does our hominid ancestor grasp the femur, but they grasp, as well, an important application. Squatting among the skeletal remains, femur in hand, our hominid ancestor taps the bones in exploratory manner. Each strike of the femur grows in force until finally, in a crescendo of activity, they smash the tapir's skull to pieces. Our hominid ancestor has reached a crucial insight, that an implement, such as the femur, might transform tapir into prey. Moreover, the application generalizes. The femur might also be used as a weapon against competing groups of hominids. The acquired technology thus has political consequences. What is presently important, however, is the connection between grasping and cognition. We say we have grasped a situation when we have understood it. And philosophers are prone to speak of thinkers grasping the thoughts they think. Kubrick dramatizes the connection between grasping and cognition by having our hominid ancestor's grasping the femur among the tapir's skeletal remains be the primal scene of a dawning understanding.
We have \emph{grasped} a situation when we have understood it. We have a \emph{grip} on it. If the understanding in question is practical, we might say that we have matters \emph{in hand}. And we \emph{touch upon} subjects for discussion. Nor are tactile metaphors confined to forms of higher cognition and their expression in rational discourse. They persist, as well, in our description of perceptual awareness. Not only do we speak of recognizing an object that we see as \emph{grasping} the object present in our perceptual experience, but the presentation in experience is itself a kind of grasping. In perceiving an object we \emph{apprehend} it. In this way, perception puts us in \emph{contact} with its object. The tactile metaphors for perceptual awareness tend, on the whole, to be modes of assimilation, and \emph{ingestion} is a natural variant (see \citealt{Johnston:2006uq,Price:1932fk}), as when we \emph{drink in} the scene. Thus, for example, Peter John Olivi and Jacopo Zabarella use the Latin \emph{imbibere}, to drink in, to describe perceptual apprehension. While drinking in is a species of gustation and so not, strictly speaking, a species of touch, it does, however, involve a tactile component. Relatedly, our hominid ancestor, looking up from the tapir's remains, \emph{takes in} the scene before them. Indeed this metaphor is inscribed into the history of the English language---``perception'' derives from the Latin \emph{perceptio} meaning to \emph{take in} or \emph{assimilate} \citep[102]{Burnyeat:1979mv}. If in looking up from the tapir's remains, they see the obelisk, then, in a manner of speaking common among contemporary philosophers, the obelisk is the \emph{content} of our hominid ancestor's perception. But if the obelisk is the content of their perception then their perception of it is its \emph{container}. To bring something into view so that it figures in the content of perception would be to contain it within that perception. But containment itself is a mode of assimilation.
Even granting the primordial and persistent use of tactile metaphors for perception and cognition more generally, one may wonder whether grasping is really at the center of the semantic field of metaphors for sensory presentation. Grasping may involve contact, but not all contact involves grasping, not even all perceptual modes of contact. Some elements of the semantic field, such as talk of ``contact'', are logically independent of grasping. And this can raise the following worry. Perhaps for something to be present in sensory experience is for the perceiver to be in perceptual contact with it. If so, perhaps it is contact, and not grasping, that is the central metaphor for sensory presentation. Grasping, on this interpretation, is something further than the object of perception being presented in the perceiver's experience. Perhaps to grasp what we are in perceptual contact with is to recognise what perception presents us with.
The logical observation that occasioned this worry does not force upon us the alternative reading where contact is sensory presentation and grasping recognition (though, as we have observed, the metaphor of grasping can have such uses). That there can be perceptual contact without grasping is consistent with contact being an important component of grasping that is at the center of the semantic field. Thus, for example, \citet{Broad:1952kx} uses both ``contact'' and ``prehension'' for sensory presentation presumably because prehending the object of perception involves being in contact with it. Talk of contact captures the visceral immediacy of sensory presentation, its force and vivacity. Moreover, talk of contact emphasizes the existence of an external limit determined by that with which we are in contact, the experience of which, as we shall see, plays an important role in sensory presentation. Talk of grasping, on the other hand, captures other important aspects of perceptual presentation, specifically, that it is apt to think of perception as a mode of assimilation. Moreover, it will emerge that the objectivity of perception is best understood in terms of perception formally assimilating to its object in the sense that it does. In this way, the full justification for the claim that grasping is at the center of a semantic field of metaphors for sensory presentation consists in the fruits that it will bear. However, that is not all that can be said. The hypothesis that grasping is at the center of the semantic field can explain why contact is included, but the alternative hypothesis that contact is at the center of the semantic field could not explain why so many of the other metaphors are modes of assimilation.
What makes tactile metaphors for perception apt? Tactile metaphors for perceptual awareness, even for non-tactile modes of awareness such as vision and audition, are primordial and persistent. Most contemporary philosophers of perception apply them unselfconsciously, indeed, unconsciously. That they do is a testament to the power of such metaphors. Understanding the power they have over us, understanding what makes them so compelling, we may gain insight into the object of these metaphors. In understanding what makes grasping an apt metaphor for perception generally, if it is indeed one, we may gain insight into the nature of sensory presentation. Or so I suggest.
We shall begin with a phenomenological investigation into the nature of grasping, a form of haptic touch. The investigation is phenomenological in that it seeks to uncover how grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, presents itself from within tactile experience. It is phenomenological because the object of investigation is restricted to perceptual appearances and not because of any methodology deployed in pursuing that investigation. The investigation thus need not involve ``bracketing'', nor need it confine itself to the deliverances of introspection in determining the nature of haptic appearance (for discussion of the reliability of introspection see \citealt{Schwitzgebel:2008aa,Bayne:2010ca}). In trying to understand how grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, presents itself from within tactile experience, we may avail ourselves of empirical and historical resources. Once we have a better understanding of how grasping presents itself from within tactile experience, we will be in a better position to understand why grasping also presents itself as an exemplar of sensory presentation more generally.
We may avail ourselves of empirical resources since phenomenology is something about which discoveries can be made. As \citet{Hilbert:2007qy} and \citet{Phillips:2012af} argue, psychophysics can contribute to our understanding of perceptual phenomenology. Similarly, we might reasonably expect empirical research to reveal important aspects of the phenomenology of haptic perception. Indeed, as Fulkerson's \citeyearpar{Fulkerson:2014ek} argues at length, there is much to learn about the phenomenology of haptic perception from its empirical study.
% For example, Ewald Herring’s claim that there are four basic colors was not obvious upon reflection. Had it been, Hermann von Helmholtz, James Clerk Maxwell, and Thomas Young who maintained that there were three instead would have been culpably inattentive to their own color experience. But that is implausible. As a matter of fact, Herring’s basic phenomenological claims about color vision, while not without empirical support, had to wait for Hurvich and Jameson’s research for empirical confirmation.
In investigating the phenomenology of haptic perception, not only may we avail ourselves of empirical resources, but we may also avail ourselves of historical resources. If I am right that our unselfconscious, indeed, unconscious, use of tactile metaphors for perception is best explained by their persistent aptness, then looking at early historical examples of these metaphors, when they were more vivid and strongly felt, promises to shed light on those aspects of the phenomenology of haptic experience that makes them apt.
% As Nietzsche observes:
% \begin{quote}
% The relief-like, incomplete presentation of an idea, of a whole philosophy, is sometimes more effective than its exhaustive realization: more is left for the beholder to do, he is more impelled to continue work- ing on that which appears before him so strongly etched in light and shadow, to think it through to the end, and to overcome even that constraint which has hitherto prevented it from stepping forth fully formed. (Nietzsche, \emph{Menschliches, Allzumenschliches: Ein Buch für freie Geister}, 1878, 1 4 178; \citealt{Hollingdale:1996as})
% \end{quote}
Grasping may be an apt metaphor for perception generally, and to that extent at least, an exemplar of sensory presentation, but it does not follow that all perception is a form of touch. One may grant that tactile metaphors for perceptual awareness are in some sense apt while eschewing any such reductive explanatory ambition. Such ambitions were rife in Greek antiquity. Thus \citet[39]{Lindberg:1977aa} observes that in the ancient world ``the analogy of perception by contact in the sense of touch seemed to establish to nearly everybody’s satisfaction that contact was tantamount to sensation, and it was not apparent that further explanation was required.'' Aristotle criticizes this reductive explanatory strategy. Conceiving of non-tactile modes of perceptual awareness on the model of touch will only seem explanatory insofar as touch is antecedently understood to be an unproblematic mode of perception. However, Aristotle's belaboring and not always completely resolving the \emph{aporiai} concerning touch in \emph{De anima} 2 11 undermines that assumption \citep{Derrida:2005aa,Kalderon:2015fr}. And if further explanation is required, then we can no longer simply assume that contact is tantamount to sensation. Nevertheless, Aristotle accepts the aptness of the metaphor. Perception, for Aristotle, remains a mode of assimilation. Aristotle defines perception as the assimilation of sensible form without the matter of the perceived particular (\emph{De anima} 2 12 424\( ^{a} \)18–23, 2 5 418\( ^{a} \)3–6 ). So acceptance of the aptness of the metaphor carries with it no commitment to any such reductive explanatory ambition. Grasping may be apt metaphor for perception, even for non-tactile modes of perceptual awareness, such as vision and audition, without perception being reduced to a form of touch. Indeed, if perception reduced to touch, then what strikes us as tactile metaphors for perception generally would, in truth, be no metaphors at all.
% Section grasping_and_the_dawn_of_understanding (end)
\section{Haptic Perception} % (fold)
\label{sec:haptic_perception}
Grasping is a form of haptic touch. Haptic touch involves active exploration of the tangible object. This can involve a range of different stereotypical exploratory activities often combined in sequence. The different stereotypical exploratory activities are suited to presenting different ranges of tangible qualities. Thus to discern the texture of an object the perceiver may deploy lateral movement across its surface. Holding a stone in their hand, our hominid ancestor may feel the roughness of the stone by rubbing their thumb across its surface. And its hardness may be felt by applying pressure to it. According to the taxonomy of \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, grasping is a distinctive exploratory activity that they describe as ``enclosure''. Grasping an object allows the perceiver to discern a different range of tangible qualities. If texture is perceived by lateral motion and hardness by applying pressure, grasping or enclose makes volume and global shape available in tactile experience. Other stereotypical exploratory activities include: ``static contact''---passively resting one's hand on an externally supported object, without an effort to mold to its contours, to determine its temperature, ``unsupported holding''---holding the object without external support, and without molding, to determine the object's heft or weight often involving a ``weighing'' motion, ``contour following''---a smooth, nonrepetitive tracing of the contours of the object, ``part motion test''---moving a part of the object independently of the whole, and ``specific function test''---moving the object in such a way as to perform various functions. Though these stereotypical exploratory activities are optimized for determining a specific range of tangible qualities, they can also determine other tangible qualities, though perhaps less well, with less tactual acuity. Thus while grasping or enclosure may present the overall shape of the object, to determine its exact shape the perceiver must use contour following. Grasping however, like contour following, is relatively general in the range of tangible qualities it can present. Thus, grasping is itself a way of applying pressure to an object and, hence, a way of perceiving its hardness, as well as other of the object's tangible qualities such as temperature, moistness, vibration, a metallic feel, and so on. Not only are these stereotypical exploratory activities optimized to determine a specific range of tangible qualities that vary in generality, but they can also be chained together to provide the perceiver with a more complete profile of the corporeal aspects of the object under investigation.
% (I say ``metallic feel'' rather than ``metallic'', since non-metallic things can have a metallic feel, there to be felt if only we grasp them.)
With enclosure, Lederman and Klatzky write:
\begin{quote}
\ldots the hand maintains simultaneous contact with as much of the envelope of the object as possible. Often one can see an effort to mold the hand more precisely to object contours. Periods of static enclosure may alternate with shifts of the object in the hand(s). \citep[346--7]{Lederman:1987fr}
\end{quote}
The quoted passage brings out several important features of grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception.
First, grasping a rigid, solid body involves the hand's maintaining simultaneous contact with as much of its overall surface as possible. Grasping is thus a kind of incorporation. Recall, what unites the various tactile metaphors for perception, even for non-tactile modes of perceptual awareness such as vision and audition, is that they tend to be modes of assimilation, and grasping exemplifies this pattern. It may not be as complete an incorporation as the variant, ingestion, but it remains a clear mode of assimilation nonetheless. In maintaining simultaneous contact with as much of its overall surface as possible, the hand assimilates to the contours of the object. As we shall see, that the grasping hand assimilates to the object grasped is a manifestation of the objectivity of that haptic perception. This is part of what it makes it an apt metaphor for perceptual presentation more generally.
Second, not only does the grasping hand assimilate to the overall shape and volume of the object grasped, but, as \citet{Lederman:1987fr} observe, effort is typically exerted to mold the hand more precisely to the object's contours. So grasping or enclosure involves not only the hand's configuration in maintaining simultaneous contact with the overall surface of the object, but the force of the hand's activity as well. Not only is this force exerted in achieving the end of molding the hand more perfectly to contours of the object grasped (on the preparatory reach involved in grasping see \citealt[Chapter 6]{Jones:2006aa}), but it is exerted as well in the end's achievement---maintaining simultaneous contact with the overall surface of the object requires continued effort to sustain. This is physiologically and phenomenologically significant. It is physiologically significant in that the activation of different sets of receptors are coordinated in haptic perception (see \citealt[Chapter 1]{Hatwell:2003dn} and \citealt[Chapter 3, for discussion]{Fulkerson:2014ek}). Grasping or enclosure will involve not only cutaneous activation but also the distinct sets of activations involved in kinesthesis, motor control, and our sense of agency. Moreover, this is reflected in our phenomenology. We feel the force with which we grip the object as well as the object's overall shape and volume.
Third, there is tendency, in grasping or enclosure, to shift the object periodically in one's hands. What explains this? Begin with Lederman's and Klatzky's \citeyearpar{Lederman:1987fr} observation that there is a tendency for perceivers to exert effort to mold their hand more precisely to the contours of the object grasped. In grasping an object, the grasping hand in this way assimilates to the overall shape and volume of the object grasped. Consider grasping a solid, rigid body, such as a stone. In grasping a stone, our hominid ancestor extends their hand's activity, they tighten their grasp, until they can no more. Since the stone is solid, it resists penetration. Since it is rigid, it maintains its overall shape and volume even when in the hominid's grasp. Contrast the way the overall shape and volume of an elastic body, such a sponge, deforms as it is squeezed. With the stone in its grip, the hand of our hominid ancestor assimilates to the overall shape and volume of the stone. Of course, hands are unevenly shaped and imperfectly elastic. This means that an effort to mold one's hand to a rigid, solid body thus disclosing its overall shape and volume will most likely be imperfectly realized. There may be some areas of the object's surface that the grasping hand does not conform to. Haptic perception is thus partial in something like Hilbert's \citeyearpar{Hilbert:1987jq} sense. Perception is partial if the object of perception is not wholly present in the awareness of it afforded by perceptual experience. There may be more to the object of perception, even in its sensible aspects, than is determined in any given perception. The tendency to shift the grasped object in our hands compensates for this partial and imperfect disclosure. In shifting the object in one's hand, an area that the hand did not previously conform to may become accessible to touch. Successive grips and the manner in which the object moves in one's hands as one shifts between them may provide a better overall sense of the shape and volume of the rigid, solid body.
I have offered an explanation of the tendency, observed by \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, for the perceiver to shift the object of haptic exploration periodically in their hands in terms of the partiality of haptic perception. That explanation is incomplete. Active exploration of the object of haptic investigation could only be motivated to compensate for its partial and imperfect disclosure if the perceiver has the sense, perhaps instinctive, that there is more to the corporeal nature of the object than is disclosed in their grasp. This is the allure of the tangible---the sense, or premonition, that, at any given moment, the body exceeds what is disclosed to us by touch. Our tactile sense of a body's ``thingness''---its concrete particularity---consists, in part, in this allure. (Compare Harman's \citeyear[141--144]{Harman:2005ag}, discussion of allure; though, for Harman, allure carries with it, not only the suggestion of hidden depths, but inaccessibility as well.) Without this primitive sense that there are further tangible aspects of the body as of yet unfelt, the partiality of haptic perception, by itself, could not explain the tendency for perceivers to shift the object of haptic investigation periodically in their hands. The partial and imperfect character of haptic disclosure must itself be disclosed in the haptic experience that affords it.
The explanation is incomplete in another way. In periodically shifting the object in their hands to compensate for the partial and imperfect disclosure of the object grasped, the perceiver's haptic experience must exhibit perceptual constancy (on the importance of constancy phenomena to understanding perception see \citealt{Smith:2002sa,Burge:2010uq}).
Very often, objects in the scene before us are somehow perceived to be constant or uniform or unchanging in color, shape, size, or position, even while their appearance with respect to these features somehow changes. This is a familiar and pervasive fact about perception, even if it is notoriously difficult to describe accurately let alone adequately account for. Perceptual constancy is not confined to vision. Importantly, it is exhibited in haptic perception as well. Thus, for example, our haptic experience of roughness exhibits perceptual constancy \citep{Yoshioka:2011aa}. The texture of a stone picked up by our hominid ancestor will feel rough, and just as rough, when felt with a quick motion as when felt with a slow motion, even though feeling the stone's rough texture with a quick motion does not feel the same as with a slow motion. Other forms of haptic perception exhibit perceptual constancy as well.
Grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, itself exhibits perceptual constancy. Thus, the perceiver feels the constant overall shape and volume of the object even though it feels different in successive grips. What the perceiver feels in moving the object between successive grips changes throughout this process, but the object disclosed by this haptic exploration is not Protean in character. If the object were changing its overall shape and volume in the process of the perceiver's handling it, then shifting the object could be no compensation for the partial and imperfect disclosure of the object grasped. If the object were Protean, and the perceiver shifted it in their hands, then its overall shape and volume would change, and the opportunity to feel what was unfelt would be forever lost.
In grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, the perceiver attends only to the constant tangible qualities it presents, in the case of a rigid, solid body, the perceiver attends to its constant overall shape and volume, as well as other constant tangible qualities that grasping may disclose. Though there may be a felt difference in changing patterns of intensive sensation in handling the object (changing patterns of pressure and thermal sensation, say), haptic experience presents the constant overall shape and volume of the object. Of course, different aspects of the overall shape and volume may be present at different times, given the different ways the body is being handled. Sensory presentation being partial, the perceiver may now feel this corner and now that. But these presented aspects of the overall shape of a rigid, solid body are experienced as stable aspects of a body that retains its shape, despite the perceiver's handling, because of the self-maintaining forces at work in its constitution. So the tendency, observed by \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, for the perceiver to periodically shift the object in their hands is not only explained by the partiality of haptic perception, but could only be so explained if the haptic experience this behavior gives rise to exhibits perceptual constancy. (Compare Matthen's \citeyear{Matthen:2015bq} discussion of the construction of isotropic perceptual models in active perception.)
Allow me to make two further observations about this passage, though now about issues that are merely implicit.
First, grasping is an activity and so is spread over time. It has duration. Not only does our hominid ancestor tentatively reach out and grasp the tapir's femur from amongst its skeletal remains---an event with duration---, but its grasp must be actively maintained over a period of time. Maintaining simultaneous contact with the overall surface of a rigid body, or some non-insignificant portion of it, is a state sustained by activity. In this regard, it is like Ryle's \citeyearpar[149]{Ryle:1949qr} example of keeping the enemy at bay, or Kripke's \citeyearpar{kripke72} example of the connection between heat and molecular motion. The state thus obtains for the duration of the sustaining activity. Moreover, in coming to perceive its overall shape and volume, the perceiver may shift the object in their hand. The tactile sense of an object's overall shape or volume is disclosed by such activity. And since activity has duration, it is disclosed over time. The presentation of the overall shape and volume of an object in tactile experience is itself spread over time like the activity that discloses it. One potential lesson, then, for the metaphysics of sensory presentation, is that the object of perception may be disclosed over time, that its presentation in perceptual experience may have duration.
Second, that the grasping hand assimilates to the overall shape and volume of the object grasped is potentially epistemically significant. The full case for this will have to wait (Section~\ref{sec:shaping} and Chapter~\ref{sec:grasping_and_the_rhetoric_of_objectivity}), but we can begin to get a sense of why this might be so. A rigid, solid body has a certain overall shape and volume prior to being grasped. Moreover, it is sufficiently rigid and solid to maintain that overall shape and volume even when grasped. In making an effort to more precisely mold the hand to the contours of the rigid, solid object, the hand thus takes on, to an approximate degree, the overall shape and volume of the object grasped. That is to say, the hand takes on a certain configuration determined by the hand's anatomy, the activity of the hand, and the overall shape of the object grasped. And with the hand so configured, the shape of its interior approximates the overall shape of the object grasped. Moreover, the hand, so configured, encompasses a region of a certain volume itself determined by the hand and the volume of the object grasped. And the volume of the region that the hand encompasses approximates the volume of the object grasped. That is the point of making an effort to more precisely mold the hand to contours of the rigid object. In engaging in such haptic activity, in molding one's hand more precisely to the contours of the object, one ensures that the overall shape and volume of the object had prior to being grasped, and maintained in being grasped, explains, in part, the hand's configuration in grasping the object and the force that needs to be exerted to maintain that configuration. Suppose that it is our hand's configuration in grasping and the force that needs to be exerted in maintaining that configuration that discloses the overall shape and volume of the object. If so, at least in the present instance, haptic perception is dependent, in some appropriate sense, upon proprioception, kinesthesis, our capacity for motor activity, and our sense of agency (for relevant discussion see \citealt{OShaughnessy:1989zp,OShaughnessy:1995ty,Martin:1992aa,Fulkerson:2014ek}; we will discuss this dependency in Chapter 2). Since the object's overall shape and volume explains the hand's configuration and force, if the object eludes the hand's grasp, then that configuration and force would not have occurred. If the object is absent, there is nothing for the hand to assimilate to. Perhaps the objectivity of grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, consists in the grasping hand's assimilating to the tangible qualities of the object had prior to grasping.
Against this suggestion, it might be objected that, at least for certain graspings, it is possible for the object to be absent and yet the hand to be in a duplicate configuration. However, a felt difference would remain. Maintaining the hand's configuration in the absence of the object requires different muscle activity since the perceiver can no longer rely on pressing against the rigid body in maintaining that configuration. The different pattern of activation of receptors in muscles and joints will result in a felt difference. Compare leaning against a wall with making as if to lean against a wall. Sustaining that posture in the absence of the supporting wall can be difficult to do. Miming is an acquired skill. As Jacques Tati demonstrates in \emph{Cours du Soir}, it can be taught and learned. So in the case of duplicate configuration, where the hand takes on the configuration it would have had if it were grasping the object, while the hand's configuration has been maintained in the absence of the object, there is a felt difference in the force exerted.
That the grasping hand assimilates to the contours of the object grasped is potentially epistemically significant. It is, if not the source of that haptic perception's objectivity, then its manifestation. In grasping an object, the hand assimilates to the object's contours. If in grasping an object, the hand's configuration and force discloses the object's overall shape and volume, and that configuration and force would not have occurred in the absence of the object grasped, then our tactile experience would not be as it is when we haptically perceive if that object were in fact absent. While not yet proof against a Cartesian demon, one can begin to see the potential epistemic significance of the effort exerted in more precisely molding one's hand against the contours of the object grasped. It is the means by which certain tangible qualities of an external body are disclosed in our grasp. We shall return to this issue in Section~\ref{sec:shaping} and again in Chapter~\ref{sec:grasping_and_the_rhetoric_of_objectivity}.
% Section haptic_perception (end)
\section{The Protagorean Model} % (fold)
\label{sec:the_protagorean_model}
We have undertaken to uncover how grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, presents itself from within tactile experience. The investigation is phenomenological in the sense that the object of investigation is restricted to perceptual appearances. Moreover, we have engaged in a phenomenological investigation into the nature of grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, in order to understand what makes grasping an apt metaphor, if it is, of perception more generally, including non-tactile modes of perception. Perhaps part of the aptness of the metaphor consists in providing a model for sensory presentation more generally. On the basis of our discussion of \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, we are now in a position to sketch, to a first approximation, the contours of such a model. It is usefully compared, if only to highlight the differences, with the conception of perception that Socrates attributes to Protagoras.
In the \emph{Theaetetus} 156 a--c, Socrates elaborates the Secret Doctrine of Protagoras by providing an account of perception as the contingent outcome of active and passive forces in conflict. Grasping as a mode of haptic perception can seem to approximate to that account. At the very least, the felt shape and volume of the object grasped is determined by conflicting forces. On the one hand, there is the force exerted in molding the hand more precisely to the contours of the rigid, solid body. On the other hand, there are the self-maintaining forces of the rigid, solid body itself. A rigid, solid body, such as a stone picked up by a hominid ancestor, is no mere sum of matter. It has a form or material structure determined by forces that are the categorical bases for its rigidity and solidity (\citealt{Johnston:2006js}; compare also Leibniz's and Kant's dynamical theories of matter). Haptic perception is the joint upshot of the force exerted by the grasping hand and the self-maintaining forces of the object grasped. There remains a crucial difference, however, from the account elaborated by Socrates. The overall shape and volume of the object and our haptic perception of them are not ``twin births'' as Protagoras maintains:
\begin{quote}
Motion has two forms, each an infinite multitude, but distinguished by their powers, the one being active and the other passive. And through the intercourse and mutual friction of these two there comes to be an offspring infinite in multitude but always twin births, on the one hand what is perceived, on the other, the perception of it, the perception in every case being generated together with what is perceived and emerging along with it. (Plato, \emph{Theaetetus} 156 a--b; Levett and Burnyeat in \citealt[173--4]{Cooper:1997fk})
\end{quote}
Aristotle's criticism of Protagoras often fits the following pattern: An important concession is made to Protagoras, only for Aristotle to argue that the concession can only be accepted on an understanding unavailable to the Protagorean (see, for example, Metaphysica \( \Gamma \) 5 1010\( ^{b} \)30–1011\( ^{a} \)2 and see \citealt[Chapter 2.1.1, for discussion]{Kalderon:2015fr}). In appropriating the Protagorean model, we shall be following Aristotle's lead.
Begin with the way in which haptic perception, as so far described, differs from the conception of perception that figures in the Secret Doctrine. The forces that determine the object's rigidity and solidity are sufficient to maintain the object's overall shape and volume within the hand's grasp. So the perceived tangible qualities of the external body inhere in that body prior to being perceived, whereas in the account attributed to Protagoras, the perceived object comes into being with the perceiver's perception of it. One might concede to Protagoras that the presentation of the object's overall shape and volume in tactile experience and the perceiver's feeling its overall shape and volume are, in fact, ``twin births''. It is at least the case that if overall shape and volume are not present in tactile experience then they are not felt, and if they are not felt, they are not present in tactile experience, at least not in that way. But not only is this consistent with perceptual realism, but it is only intelligibly sustained against the background of a realist metaphysics. If a tangible quality's presentation in tactile experience is explained, in part, by that quality inhering in the object perceived, then the object must possess this quality prior to perception. There is a connection, then, between explanatory priority and objectivity (this, I argue, is Aristotle's view, \citealt{Kalderon:2015fr}). At least with respect to grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, this perceptual realism is sustained by the force of the hand's activity in conflict with the self-maintaining forces of the object grasped. At the very least, the force of the hand's activity ensures that the tangible quality determined by the object's self-maintaining forces explains the hand's configuration and force and the haptic experience these give rise to. Explaining how this may be so is the task of this Chapter and the next.
The model of perception that has emerged from our phenomenology of haptic perception is realist and not at all relativist. Nevertheless, it remains apt to describe it as Protagorean, given the way that perception is the joint upshot of forces in conflict. To highlight this consider the following. The Protagorean model, as presently understood, is neither an extramission theory nor an intramission theory. The distinction between extramission and intramission theories arises in the historiography of perception (see, for example, \citealt[3--67]{Lindberg:1977aa}). The distinction is an historian's classification of accounts of perception. Very roughly, whereas intramission theories emphasize the passive reception of the effects, from without, of the object of perception, extramission theories emphasize, instead, outer-directed activity, such as the emanation of a visual ray in Euclid's geometrical optics. This rough characterization of the distinction is incomplete but suffices to mark the differences with the Protagorean model (a more complete characterization of extramission is given in Chapter~\ref{cha:vision}). The Protagorean model is not adequately described as either extramissive or intramissive but contains elements of each. The Protagorean model is neither extramissive nor intramissive, but is perhaps better described as interactionist (for ancient interactionism see \citealt{Squire:2016aa}). Like the extramission theory, the Protagorean model emphasizes outer-directed activity of the perceiver in the disclosure of the object of perception. Like the intramission theory, the Protagorean model emphasizes that not only does the perceiver act, but that the perceiver is acted upon, as well. The perception of what is there, prior to perception, is the joint upshot of forces in conflict. On the Protagorean model, then, perception is determined by the interaction of the perceiver and the object perceived and is thus more aptly deemed interactionist than by either of the traditional categories of the historiography of perception.
% Section the_protagorean_model (end)
\section{Assimilation} % (fold)
\label{sec:assimilation}
So far in our discussion of grasping or enclosure we have established at least one claim about the metaphysics of sensory presentation, that sensory presentation is of such a nature that its objects may be disclosed over time. \citet{Broad:1952kx} took this dynamical aspect of sensory presentation to be confined to haptic perception. This is, at best, an exaggeration. If sounds and their sources, if not their audible qualities such as pitch and timbre, are spread over time, then it is at least natural to think that their presentation in auditory experience is itself disclosed over time. Moreover, there is reason to think that the presentation in visual experience of color qualities may itself be spread over time, at least some of the time. Thus as Broackes observes:
\begin{quote}
in order to tell what colour an object is, we may try it out in a number of different lighting environments. It is not that we are trying to get it into one single `standard' lighting condition, at which point it will, so to speak, shine in its true colours. Rather, we are looking, in the way it handles a variety of different illuminations (all of which are more or less `normal'), for its constant capacity to modify light. \citep[215]{Broackes:1997pa}
\end{quote}
And similar claims connecting color perception to activity with duration have been made by \citet{Noe:2004fk} and \citet{Matthen:2005md}. Notice that perceived colors belong to a distinct ontological category than sounds and their sources. Sounds and their sources may be particulars like perceived colors, but whereas perceived colors are quality instances, sounds and their sources are events or processes. This claim is controversial. Further defence of it is given in Chapters~\ref{cha:sound} and \ref{cha:sources_of_sound}. For the moment, however, let us suppose the controversial claim to be true, if only to observe a consequence of it. Suppose that sounds and their sources that we hear are events or processes whereas the colors that we see are quality instances, but that each may be disclosed over time in our perceptual experience of them. So the fact that sensory presentation is spread over time need not be a consequence of the temporal mode of being of its object, as when a quality instance is disclosed over time. Thus our phenomenological investigation into grasping understood as a mode of haptic perception has made vivid at least one claim about the metaphysics of sensory presentation, that the presence of the object of perception may be disclosed over time in perceptual experience, that sensory presentation may have duration. Moreover, this holds not only for the sensory presentation at work in haptic perception, but plausibly, as well, for the sensory presentation at work in other sensory modalities such as audition and vision.
Though a small claim about the metaphysics of sensory presentation, it has significant consequences. To take but one example, consider the claim that our ordinary experience of the natural environment is nothing more than a Grand Illusion. When our hominid ancestor turns, and looks, and sees, they are seemingly presented with a richly detailed scene of the alien obelisk set against a cloudy dawn sky. And this is true of the experience of twenty-first century humanity as well. When we visually perceive something, we are seemingly presented with a richly detailed scene. However, empirical research into change and inattentional blindness has suggested to some psychologists and philosophers that this aspect of our phenomenology is illusory (see, for example, \citealt{Blackmore:1995an,Simons:1999wf}). Our visual experience may present itself as the presentation of a richly detailed scene, but, in fact, at any given moment, we are at best visually presented with a detail of some fragment of that scene.
In at least some cases, the reasoning for the Grand Illusion hypothesis may be resisted, for it seems to presuppose that experience only presents what could be present at any given moment. But if perceptual experience may disclose its object over time, then the claim that visual perception presents a richly detailed scene is consistent with the claim that, at any given moment, visual perception at best presents a fragment of that scene, so long as the richly detailed scene is understood to be disclosed over time and not present at a moment. Some of the arguments, then, if not all of them, for the Grand Illusion hypothesis turn on denying this claim about the metaphysics of sensory presentation---that sensory presentation may be a kind of disclosure with duration. (For recent relevant discussion see, \emph{inter alia}, \citealt{Noe:2004fk}, \citealt[72--74]{Campbell:2014aa})
Our first claim about the metaphysics of sensory presentation involved a literal feature of grasping or enclosure. Grasping is a mode of haptic perception, and the presentation of its object is spread over time. That observation suffices to establish that sensory presentation may be a kind of disclosure with duration. Consider now another feature of grasping or enclosure, that the grasping hand assimilates to the rigid, solid body in its grasp. The hand's assimilating to the overall shape and volume of the object grasped is a manifestation, if not the source, of that haptic perception's objectivity. This, I suggested, is part of what makes grasping or enclosure an apt metaphor for sensory presentation more generally. It is important to get clearer about what this assimilation amounts to, and how it may be generalized, if assimilation is genuinely part of what makes grasping an apt metaphor for sensory presentation.
Grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, is, like the variant meta\-phor, ingestion, a kind of incorporation. This can suggest that the mode of assimilation is material---that it is a taking in, or incorporation, of a material body. Thus, for example, in eating an olive, the matter of the olive is taken in and presented to the organ of taste and thereby tasted. But while some forms of sensory perception involve material assimilation such as tasting, not all do. Vision and audition involve the material assimilation of no thing. So if the assimilation at work in grasping or enclosure is part of what makes it an apt metaphor for sensory presentation generally, it must be understood in some other way.
Perhaps, the assimilation at work in grasping or enclosure is not merely material but formal. Whereas material assimilation involves the taking in, or incorporation, of a material body, formal assimilation involves the assimilation of nothing material. Formal assimilation, instead, involves taking on the form, if not the matter, of an object, by becoming like it, at least in some respect. In grasping or enclosure, the hand formally assimilates to the contours of the object grasped. The interior of the hand thus approximates to the overall shape of the object, and the volume it encloses approximates to the object's volume. The shape of the interior of the hand is similar to the overall shape of the object, and the volume of the region it encloses is similar to the volume of that object. Perhaps, in this way, the hand assimilates the tangible form of the object grasped, by becoming like it. However, while our hand may be warmed when feeling the warmth of an object, our eyes do not become red when viewing a traditional English phone booth. Such a view, however, has been attributed to Aristotle by \citet{Slakey:1961ss}, \citet{Sorabji:1974fk}, and \citet{Everson:1997ep}. I have my doubts \citep{Kalderon:2015fr}. Thus Theophrastus, Aristotle's student and successor at the Lyceum, in inquiring into his master's definition of perception as the assimilation of form without matter, similarly judged it absurd if it is the sense organ that is meant to become like the object of perception, and this prompted Theophrastus to understand Aristotle's definition in some other way, in a commentary now lost though reported by Priscian in \emph{Metaphrasis} 1.3–8 and referred to by Themistius, \emph{In de anima} 3 5 108. Regardless of how Aristotle is best interpreted, if Theophrastus is right that it is absurd that the eye becomes red in seeing a red thing, then formal assimilation can seem no better off than material assimilation in this regard.
However, this latter problem for assimilation understood formally, if not materially, may be avoided by means of a small generalization. In grasping an object, where is the overall shape and volume that you feel? If grasping is a mode of haptic perception, then surely they are in the object that you grasp. Now, where is your haptic experience of that object? In your head? That answer seems so implausible on its face that only a philosopher could believe it. If anywhere, it seems more reasonable to suppose, at least initially, that it is closer to where the overall shape and volume are felt, in your handling of the object. Perhaps in trying to come to an understanding of formal assimilation at work in grasping or enclosure that may be generalized to other sensory modalities, we focussed too closely on the shape of the interior of the hand and the volume it encloses. If our haptic experience is where we handle the object grasped, perhaps the similarity obtains not only between the hand and certain tangible qualities of the object, but between the haptic experience that the hand's activity gives rise to and the tangible qualities presented in it. Haptic experience, like perceptual experience more generally, has a conscious qualitative character. Perhaps, in grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, the phenomenological character of haptic experience formally assimilates to the tangible qualities presented in it. And, arguably at least, this feature, suitably qualified, is generalizable to other sensory modalities as well---that in sensory perception quite generally, the phenomenological character of perceptual experience formally assimilates to the object presented in it.
Before considering whether that generalization partly grounds the aptness of grasping or enclosure as a metaphor for sensory presentation, even for non-tactile modes of perceptual awareness such as vision and audition, let us look closer at formal assimilation at work in haptic perception. Earlier we noted that haptic perception, like perception generally, is partial. The partial character of grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, explained the tendency, observed by \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, for the perceiver to shift the object of haptic exploration periodically in their hands. Such behavior compensates for the partial and imperfect disclosure of the overall shape and volume of the object grasped. Successive grips and the manner in which the object moves in one's hands provide a more complete profile of the corporeal aspects of the object under investigation. If the successive grips disclose different aspects of the object's overall shape and volume, then they provide something like different haptic perspectives on the object grasped.
While talk of ``perspective'' derives from the case of vision, a clear analogue of that notion finds application in the haptic case. To the extent that it does, then talk of ``haptic perspective'', while in a sense visuocentric, is not pejoratively so (on visuocentrism in philosophy of perception see \citealt{OCallaghan:2007xy}, for the critique of ``occularcentrism'' in twentieth century French thought see \citealt{Jay:1994aa}).
To appreciate this, let us first get clearer on some salient features of visual perspective. Our hominid ancestor, looking up from the skeletal remains of the tapir, sees the alien obelisk. In seeing the obelisk, our hominid ancestor has a perspective on it. Their perspective occurs in a space that encompasses the object seen, the alien obelisk. The space is extrapersonal. It is also ego-centrically structured. Thus, from our hominid ancestor's perspective, there are things to the left of the alien obelisk and to the right of it. At least for things that exist independently of our awareness of them, such as the obelisk, multiple perspectives on it are possible. (This is part of the reason we cannot have a perspective on a headache or a phosphene.) For there to be multiple perspectives on a thing, not only is it necessary that it should exist independently of our awareness, but it should be complex as opposed to simple. Importantly, more or less of an object may be disclosed in the multiple perspectives on it. Perspectives can reveal things to the perceiver's view, but they can equally obscure things. That aspect of the alien obelisk that is presented to our hominid ancestor's perspective is hidden from view from another perspective, when viewed from behind, say. So not only can we have multiple perspectives on things that are independent of our awareness of them, but perspectives can reveal what was potentially hidden from view. Compelled by curiosity, our hominid ancestor approaches the alien obelisk and cautiously moves around it. In so doing, the obelisk is presented to different perspectives on it adopted by our hominid ancestor in their cursory investigation. There are better and worse perspectives on the obelisk. Our hominid ancestor initially approaches to the obelisk to get a better view. Moreover, the obelisk appears different, when presented to these different perspectives, though our hominid ancestor can perceive the constant unaltered obelisk that persists in their experience of it despite these variable appearances.
All of these features find analogues in the haptic case. There will be differences, of course, but enough of a pattern may be found that warrants talk of haptic perspectives. Just as visual perspectives occur in an ego-centrically structured space, haptic perspectives occur in an ego-centrically structured space. Though, as we shall see, while, visual perspectives occur in an extrapersonal space, haptic perspectives occur in a peripersonal space. Just as there are multiple perspectives on complex visible objects that are independent of our visual awareness of them, there are multiple perspectives on complex tangible objects that are independent of our haptic awareness of them. Moreover, like visual perspectives, haptic perspectives may disclose aspects of a thing's corporeal nature hidden from other haptic perspectives. Just as there are better and worse perspectives on the visible features of things, there are better and worse haptic perspectives on the tangible features of the object of haptic investigation. And a perceiver's haptic perspective on the object of haptic investigation is manifest in its haptic appearance. A body will feel differently when presented to different haptic perspectives.
Suppose a rigid, solid body is irregularly shaped, then it potentially feels different in successive grips. And in the case of contour following, different paths may be followed, and at different rates, giving rise to different progressions of intensive sensation, themselves constituting different haptic perspectives on the constant contour of the object of haptic investigation. In a part motion test on a set of keys, the perceiver may pick up a single key and move it to the left or to the right. They may even lift it straight up and jiggle the keys thus performing a specific function test. And we may pinch, squeeze, and pull on the object of haptic investigation and these distinct activities provide us with distinct haptic perspectives on that object.
Like visual perspective, haptic perspective occurs in an ego-centrically structured space. However, whereas visual perspective presents visible aspects of extrapersonal space, haptic perspective presents tangible aspects of peripersonal space. (Deleuze's and Guattari's \citeyear[Chapter 14]{Deleuze:1987rr} discussion of smooth and striated space makes an interesting comparison here.) Peripersonal space is the space within which the perceiver may immediately act with their limbs. The representation of peripersonal space is thus linked with our motor capacity and our sense of agency. There is some evidence that human psychology operates with a representation of peripersonal space distinct from a representation of extrapersonal space \citep{Halligan:1991yf}.
% Merleau-Ponty provides the following evocative description:
% \begin{quote}
% A system of possible movements, or `motor projects,' radiates from us to our environment. Our body is not in space like things; it inhabits or haunts space. \citep[5]{Merleau-Ponty:1964ab}
% \end{quote}
Grasping, contour following, part motion and specific function tests are all activities taking place in peripersonal space. So distinct haptic activities that constitute distinct haptic perspectives on the object under investigation occur in an ego-centrically structured peripersonal space. (See, for example, Benedetti's \citeyear{Benedetti:1985qe} explanation of the Aristotle Illusion---so called, because it was first described by Aristotle in \emph{Metaphysica} \( \Delta \) 6 and \emph{De Insomniis} 2---from which \citealt[524]{Benedetti:1985qe} concludes that ``tactile stimuli are located in the body reference system according to the only available kinesthetic information, namely, the limit of the fingers' range of action''.) Like visual perspectives on objects that exist independently of our visual awareness of them, there are multiple haptic perspectives on objects that exist independently of our haptic awareness of them. That is to say that there are multiple ways to interact with the object of haptic investigation in peripersonal space. Moreover, different events in peripersonal space, different haptic interactions with the external body, disclose different tangible aspects of that body. So the haptic activities occurring in an ego-centrically structured peripersonal space can disclose previously hidden aspects of the object of haptic investigation. As we have seen, different sterotypical exploratory activities occurring in peripersonal space are suited to presenting different ranges of tangible qualities. Moreover, different stereotypical exploratory activities may determine the same tangible quality though with different tactile acuity. There are thus better and worse haptic perspectives on the tangible features of things. Moreover, different haptic perspectives, different ways of interacting with the object of haptic investigation in peripersonal space, give rise to different haptic appearances of the same object. A body may be experienced as retaining its overall shape and volume throughout the perceiver's handling of it, but it feels different in different grips.
This perspectival relativity bears on our understanding of the formal assimilation at work in grasping understood as a mode of haptic perception. In haptic perception, the tangible qualities of the object are presented to the perceiver's haptic perspective on that object---the distinctive way they are handling that object in the given circumstances---and this is reflected in the conscious character of their haptic experience. So with respect to grasping or enclosure understood as a mode of haptic perception, the doctrine of formal assimilation should be understood as the claim that the phenomenological character of haptic experience formally assimilates to the tangible qualities presented to the perceiver's haptic perspective. Na\"{i}ve realists and disjunctivists accept something like this view if not the Peripatetic vocabulary with which I have described it. Thus na\"{i}ve realists and disjunctivists are prone to speak of the phenomenological character of perceptual experience being shaped by the object as presented to the perceiver's partial perspective (see \citealt{McDowell:1998vn,Martin:2004fj,Fish:2009fk,Kalderon:2011fk}; see also Nagel's \citeyear{Nagel:1979fk} conception of perceptual experience as contrasted with \citealt{Jackson:1982my}).
It might be objected that haptic experience formally assimilating to the tangible qualities presented in it is absurd on its face. Perhaps in grasping a cube, my hand will approximate to a cube shape, but is it really the case that my experience is cube shaped, even approximately? The claim that in seeing an English phone booth my visual experience becomes red seems even worse than the view literalists attribute to Aristotle, that in seeing the phone booth my eye becomes red. What does it even mean for an experience to be cubical or red? A point that Theophrastus also makes (Priscian, \emph{Metaphrasis} 1.3–8). Although, something like this conclusion was embraced by William Crathorn in his commentary on Lombard's \emph{Sentences}: ``A soul seeing and intellectively cognizing color is truly colored,'' (\emph{Quaestiones super librum Sententiarum} q. 1 concl. 7 \citealt[288]{Pasnau:2002pb}); thus prompting Robert Holcot to compare the soul, as Crathorn conceived of it, to a chameleon (see \citealt[Chapter 1.1]{Pasnau:1997aa} for discussion).
It is important in this regard to recognize that the posited similarity need not be exact. It is only on that assumption that the similarity involved in formal assimilation involves the sharing of qualities. But if we abandon that assumption, then there is a clear sense in which, in color vision say, in seeing the phone booth, the conscious qualitative character of my color experience depends upon and derives from the qualitative character of the color presented in that experience relative to my perspective on it in the circumstances of perception (for defense of this claim see \citealt{Kalderon:2008fk,Kalderon:2007mr,Kalderon:2011fk}). And similarly we might say that in haptic perception, the conscious qualitative character of haptic experience depends upon and derives from the tangible qualities present in that experience relative to the perceiver's perspective on the object of haptic investigation, the distinctive way that they are handling it in the circumstances of perception.
Consider again the claim that haptic experience only formally assimilates to the tangible object it presents relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective. The perspectival relativity of formal assimilation bears on the inexactness of the similarity between experience and its object. The assimilation is formal in that, not only the shape of the interior of the hand and the region it encloses is similar to the overall shape and volume of the object, but the haptic experience, its conscious qualitative character, is similar to the tangible object at least as it is presented to the perceiver's haptic perspective. However, this does not require that the similarity be exact. The perspective relativity of formal assimilation nicely brings this out. Thus an irregularly-shaped, rigid, solid body, thanks to the self-maintaining forces that constitute the categorical bases of its rigidity and solidity, maintains its overall shape and volume despite progressive handling and the successive grips with which it is held. But that same shape feels different with different grips. If the phenomenological character of haptic experience were wholly determined by the tangible qualities presented in it, then we would be hard pressed to explain why this should be so.
Earlier I claimed that the partiality of haptic perception only explained the tendency, observed by \citet{Lederman:1987fr}, for the perceiver to periodically shift the object in their hands if the haptic experience this behavior gives rise to exhibits perceptual constancy. One of the philosophical challenges posed by perceptual constancy is to adequately describe and explain the phenomenology of stability and flux. In cases of perceptual constancy, a constant unaltered object of perception is presented though its appearance varies. In explaining perceptual constancy, it is not enough to determine the constant object of perception. That object continues to present itself unchanged even though its appearance may vary with a change in the perceiver's perspective or circumstances of perception. In determining only the constant object of perception, one explains the phenomenology of stability at the expense of the contribution to our phenomenology of flux (for discussion in the color case, see \citealt{Cohen:2008hc,Hilbert:2007qy}; perhaps \citealt[98]{Fulkerson:2014ek}, falls prey to this error in his account of haptic perceptual constancy, Chapter~\ref{sec:the_dependence_of_haptic_perception_upon_bodily_awareness}). Even if, in the case of grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, we attend only to the constant overall shape and volume of the object grasped, these feel differently in different successive grips. Accommodating the contribution of flux to our phenomenology of grasping or enclosure requires acknowledging that haptic presentation, like sensory presentation more generally, is perspective relative.
Haptic experience formally assimilates to its object, relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective on it, the distinctive way that they are handling that object in the circumstances of perception. Suppose that this feature of haptic perception generalizes to other modes of perception---that, in general, perceptual experience formally assimilates to its object, relative to the perceiver's partial perspective. The resulting conception of perception would be, to that extent at least, anti-modern. One fundamental feature of the early modern conception of perception is the denial of the formal assimilation of perception to its object, even relative to the perceiver's partial perspective. For at least with respect to, in Peripatetic vocabulary, the proper objects of perception, there is nothing in the external object that resembles the perceiver's perceptual experience of it. Secondary qualities are the eighteenth-century avatar of Aristotelian proper objects. And there was something like an early modern consensus that there is nothing in the external object that resembles our experience of secondary qualities. That is one of the lessons that Descartes draws, in \emph{La Dioptrique}, from the Stoic analogy between a perceiver and a blind man with a stick and, in the \emph{Second Meditation}, from the wax argument. And it is a lesson preserved by Locke. Though aspects of external objects may be found to resemble our experience of their primary qualities, nothing in such objects resembles our experience of their secondary qualities. On the early modern conception of perceptual experience, there is nothing in the obelisk that resembles our hominid ancestor's idea or sensation of its blackness. And if there is nothing in the obelisk that resembles our hominid ancestor's idea or sensation of its blackness, then their perception of its blackness could not consist in their perceptual experience formally assimilating to its object, even relative to their perspective on it. There is nothing to formally assimilate to, and, hence, no formal assimilation to constitute the perception. And if secondary quality perception cannot be understood as a mode of formal assimilation, then sensory presentation, generally, cannot be understood as essentially involving the perceiver's experience formally assimilating to its object, relative to their partial perspective on it in the circumstances of perception.
% assimilation (end)
\section{Shaping} % (fold)
\label{sec:shaping}
So far we have distinguished material and formal modes of assimilation, and have suggested that while grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, involves material assimilation---it is a kind of incorporation---, its objectivity is connected to the way in which the hand and haptic experience more generally formally assimilates to its object. Moreover, we have emphasized the way that the similarity involved in formal assimilation need not be exact so as to involve the sharing of qualities. And we have explained how the inexact similarity is related to the formal assimilation's perspectival relativity. We now turn to another important distinction. Consider Lederman's and Klatzky's \citeyearpar{Lederman:1987fr} claim that that grasping or enclosure involves molding one's hand to the contours of the object grasped. Molding is a kind of shaping. And there are causal and constitutive senses of shaping that can be distinguished. Correspondingly, there are causal and constitutive explanations of perception's formal assimilation to its object.
So consider the way that the Nazi air campaign shaped the London skyline. The destructive impact of the bombing caused the London skyline to be shaped in a certain way. This contrasts sharply with the way that St Paul's shapes the London skyline, as Herbert Mason's iconic photograph of 29 December 1940 dramatically demonstrates. St Paul's defiantly shapes the London skyline by being part of it despite the devastating impact of the bombing campaign. Whereas Nazi bombing shaped the London skyline in a merely causal sense, St Paul's constitutively shapes that skyline by being a part or contour of it.
The causal--constitutive distinction plays out, I believe, in the use that Aristotle makes of Plato's wax analogy from the \emph{Theaetetus}. Plato, in the \emph{Theaetetus}, appeals to an impression made on wax as an analogy for the operation of memory in the context of explaining how error in judgment is possible:
\begin{quote}
We may look upon it, then, as a gift of Memory, the mother of the Muses. We make impressions upon this of everything we wish to remember among the things we have seen or heard or thought of ourselves; we hold the wax under our perceptions and thoughts and take a stamp from them, in the way in which we take the imprints of signet rings. Whatever is impressed upon the wax we remember and know so long as the image remains in the wax; whatever is obliterated or cannot be impressed, we forget and do not know. (Plato, \emph{Theaetetus} 191 d--e, Levett and Burnyeat in \citealt[212]{Cooper:1997fk})
\end{quote}
In \emph{De anima}, Aristotle uses the wax analogy, not for memory and knowledge as Plato does, but for explaining his definition of perception as the assimilation of the sensible form without the matter of the perceived particular:
\begin{quote}
Generally, about all perception, we can say that a sense is what has the power of receiving into itself the sensible forms of things without the matter, in the way in which a piece of wax takes on the impress of a signet-ring without the iron or gold. (Aristotle, \emph{De anima} 2 12 424a18–23; Smith in \citealt[42--43]{Barnes:1984uq})
\end{quote}
Part of the point of using Plato's wax analogy, not for memory or knowledge, but for perception is to highlight that Aristotle is assigning to perception functions that Plato assigned only to reason. (For discussion of how far Aristotle departs from Plato in drawing the distinction between perception and cognition see \citealt{Sorabji:1971fr,Sorabji:2003fk}.)
% Consider just one example. On the conception of perception in the \emph{Theaetetus}, the objects of perception are restricted to, in Peripatetic vocabulary, the proper sensibles. Perception just is the the power to present colors and sounds, and so on (\emph{Theaetetus} 184 e 8--185 a 3). According to Plato, while color may be presented in sight through the eyes, and sound in hearing through the ears, it is only reason which distinguishes color from sound (\emph{Theaetetus} 185 a--185 e). However, according to Aristotle, we perceive the difference between color and sound. And since he denies that the capacities of vision and audition suffice for the capacity to perceive the difference between color and sound, Aristotle is committed to extramodal perception (for contemporary discussion of extramodal perception see \citealt{OCallaghan:2015ty}). So part of the point of deploying Plato's wax analogy to perception instead of forms of judgment is to emphasize that Aristotle is assigning to perception some of the functions that Plato assigned to reason.
There is a further, and for present purposes, more important way in which Aristotle departs from Plato's use of the wax analogy. There is a sense in which he takes the signet ring in the analogy more seriously than Plato. Or rather, Aristotle takes seriously, in a way that Plato does not, the distinctive discursive role of signet rings as opposed to a stylus, say. Moreover, this makes a difference to how the shaping of the wax by the ring is to be understood. Whereas Plato has in mind a causal notion of shaping, Aristotle has in mind the constitutive notion (or at least, so I argue \citealt[Chapter 9]{Kalderon:2015fr}). Plato’s explanation of the reliability of memory crucially relies on causal features of the situation. An object’s impression is the effect it has on the mind’s wax. So the operation of peoples' memories may vary as to how hard or soft their mind's wax is, or how pure or impure it is, since these features causally bear on how clear an impression the object will produce and how long it may persist in the mind's wax.
If, however, we reflect on the distinctive discursive role of a signet ring over a stylus, say, this can motivate the alternative, constitutive understanding of shaping. Notice that the impression of a signet ring plays a similar role to a signature. Thus Caston writes:
\begin{quote}
A signet produces a \emph{sealing}, an impression that establishes the identity of its owner and consequently his authority, rights, and prerogatives. When a sealing is placed on a document, especially for legal or official use, it authorizes the claims, obligations, promises, or orders made therein. A sealing thus differs from other impressions in that it \emph{purports to originate from a particular signet}. The wax thus receives the `golden or brazen signet' \ldots\ which is representative of the office or person to whom the signet belongs. \citep[302]{Caston:2005cr}
\end{quote}
Signet rings and styli thus have distinctive discursive roles. The impression made by a stylus is not linked to its legitimate possessor---one scribe may borrow another scribe’s stylus---the way an impression sealed by a signet ring is.
% Just as a signature is linked to the particular person whose signature it is, the impression sealed upon the wax by a signet ring is linked to the legitimate possessor of that ring. Moreover, signatures, like sealed impressions, carry a certain authority, the authority endowed by their legitimate possessors. Of course, signatures can be forged, as can signet rings, which can also be stolen, but these practices gain there point precisely by the link between a signature and sealed impression, on the one hand, and their legitimate possessors, on the other.
Taking this feature of the analogy seriously has an important consequence for how sensory impressions are individuated. Just as a forged signature is not my signature, an impression sealed by a forged ring, or by a stolen ring, is not the seal of the ring’s legitimate possessor. Impressions are individuated by their legitimate sources. If this feature of the analogy carries over, then perceptions, conceived on the model of sealed impressions, are individuated by their objects which are their source. A perception of Castor and a perception of Pollux are different perceptions, no matter how closely the twins may resemble one another. Castor may be a perfect duplicate of Pollux, but my impression of Castor is not an impression of Pollux. If I grasp his hand, it is Castor's hand I grasp, not Pollux's. My tactile impression of Castor is not thereby an tactile impression of Pollux, even if they feel the same.
% Just as a forged seal is not my seal, a perception of Castor is not a perception of Pollux. A forged seal may be a perfect duplicate of a genuine seal but it is not the seal of the ring’s legitimate possessor.
Notice that a causal understanding of sensory impressions, as merely the effects of causal shaping, does not have this consequence. If, as Hume maintained, cause and effect are contingently connected, the same effect, the same impression, could have been produced by a different cause. Sensory impressions, understood as the effects of causal shaping, are not individuated by their causes. If sensory impressions are individuated by their objects which are their sources, they cannot be understood as merely the effects of causal shaping.
What taking seriously the distinctive discursive role of the signet ring in the wax analogy brings out is that the formal assimilation at work in haptic perception and, arguably at least, in perception more generally, might be understood, not on the model of causal shaping, but rather on the model of constitutive shaping. If sensory impressions are individuated by their objects, perhaps these objects shape sensory consciousness not causally, or at least not merely. Perhaps in being individuated by their objects, these objects constitutively shape our sensory impressions of them (for contemporary discussion of this suggestion see \citealt{Kalderon:2008fk,Kalderon:2007mr,Kalderon:2011fk}). Recall that the assimilation at work in grasping or enclosure understood as a mode of haptic perception is formal in that, not only the shape of the interior of the hand and the region it encloses is similar to the overall shape and volume of the object grasped, but that the haptic experience, its conscious qualitative character, is similar to the tangible object at least as it is presented to the perceiver’s haptic perspective. On the causal model, a haptic experience, with its conscious qualitative character, is a sensory impression caused in a perceiver with an appropriate sensibility by the object of haptic investigation. Moreover, if the causal structure of the world cooperates and the circumstances of perception are propitious, then the conscious qualitative character of the haptic experience may be like, if not exactly like, the qualitative character of the tangible object. (Locke thinks something like this about primary quality perception.) On the constitutive model, haptic experience formally assimilates to its tangible object as well. However, that object does not merely cause the perceiver to undergo a haptic experience with a certain conscious qualitative character. Rather, corporeal aspects of the object constitutively shape the perceiver's haptic experience of it. Not only does the perceiver's haptic experience formally assimilate to its tangible object relative to their haptic perspective, in the sense that the conscious qualitative character of the experience is like, if not exactly like, the qualitative character of the tangible object present in it, but the tangible quality present in their haptic experience constitutively shapes that experience. The conscious qualitative character of the haptic experience depends upon and derives from, at least in part, the tangible qualitative character of object had prior to haptic investigation. If something feels metallic, and this is a case of tactile perception, then not only is this because of its metallic feel, but something's feeling metallic is also constituted, in part, by that metallic feel. The metallic feel of the thing is felt in it and in conformity with it. That is just what it is for something to be present in tactile experience.
In grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, the hand maintains simultaneous contact with as much of the overall surface of the object as possible. Grasping is a kind of incorporation, and thus a material mode of assimilation. Moreover, in grasping, the hand is so configured that it approximates to the contours of the object. Just as the shape of the interior of the hand and the region it encloses is like, if not exactly like, the overall shape and volume of the object grasped, the phenomenological character of the haptic experience, its conscious qualitative character, is like, if not exactly like the overall shape and volume presented to the perceiver's haptic perspective, the particular way they are handling the object. Moreover, the shaping involved, at least in the latter formal assimilation, is not merely causal but constitutive. The conscious qualitative character of the haptic experience is constituted, in part, by the tangible qualities presented to their haptic perspective.
While not all modes of perception involve material modes of assimilation, arguably at least, the formal assimilation of haptic experience to its object relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective generalizes to other modes of perception. The conscious qualitative character of perceptual experience is constituted, in part, by the qualitative character of the object presented to the perceiver's partial perspective. Our hominid ancestor turns, and looks, and sees the alien obelisk set against a cloudy dawn sky. The blackness of the obelisk is a constituent of their visual experience. The blackness of the obelisk is a constituent of their experience insofar as that experience involves the presentation of that blackness in the visual awareness afforded them by their experience of that scene. And since the experience of our hominid ancestor is constitutively linked to the blackness of the alien obelisk---an awful darkness in which stars may appear---the obelisk’s blackness shapes the contours of their visual consciousness by being present in that consciousness. The blackness of the obelisk shapes the contours of their visual experience in the way that St Paul’s defiantly shapes the London skyline, the Shard notwithstanding, simply by being present.
If this feature of grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, generalizes to other modes of perception, then it is easy to see its epistemic significance. If perception involves becoming like the perceived object actually is, then it is a genuine mode of awareness. One can only perceptually assimilate what is there to be assimilated. If perceptual experience is a formal mode of assimilation understood as a kind of constitutive shaping, then one could not undergo such an experience consistent with a Cartesian demon eliminating the object of that experience. If there is no external object, then there is nothing to which the perceiver, or perhaps their experience, can assimilate to. If the phenomenological character of perception is constitutively shaped by the object presented to the perceiver's partial perspective, then we can begin to see the epistemic significance of perceptual phenomenology. If the phenomenological character of perception is constitutively shaped by the object presented to the perceiver's partial perspective, then it is the grounds for an epistemic warrant for the range of propositions whose truth turns on what is presented in that perceptual experience (see Chapter~\ref{sec:perceptual_objectivity}).
Earlier, in Section~\ref{sec:haptic_perception}, I claimed that the effort exerted in more precisely molding one's hand against the contours of the object grasped was not yet proof against a Cartesian demon. How is this consistent with what is now being claimed? Notice the earlier claim was essentially a claim about the hand's formal assimilation to the object of haptic investigation in grasping or enclosure. What is distinctive about modern skepticism is that it counts the perceiver's body as an aspect of the external world and so doubts about the external world comprise the body as well. As \citet{Burnyeat:1982mz} argues, skeptical doubts about the existence of our bodies was not so much as entertained in the ancient world. So the felt force of one's hand in molding to the contours of the object grasped is no proof against a Cartesian demon since the hand falls within the scope of the external world and thus is cast into doubt by the demon hypothesis. (The rhetorical genius of Moore's \citeyear{Moore:1903uo} example, ``This is a hand'', turns precisely on this point or, rather, precisely calls this point into question.) However, the present discussion is not about the hand's formal assimilation to the object of haptic perception, but about the formal assimilation of the haptic experience, that the hand's activity gives rise to, to the object presented in it. Haptic experience, and conscious experience more generally, is not within the purview of the skeptical doubt licensed by the demon hypothesis. But if haptic experience is constituted, even in part, by tangible aspects of an external body, then haptic experience contains within itself tangible aspects of the external body, so there is no room for the possibility of eliminating that body while leaving experience as it is. Just as the hand incorporates its object in grasping or enclosure, the haptic experience that this activity gives rise to is itself a kind of incorporation, in a different, metaphorical, and anti-Cartesian sense.
Haptic experience is a kind of incorporation, in the metaphorical sense, insofar as its formal assimilation to its object, relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective, is understood on the model of constitutive shaping. If haptic experience is, in this way, a kind of incorporation, the resulting conception of experience is anti-modern. Descartes, by contrast, models sensory experience on bodily sensations, such as tickles and pains (\emph{Le Monde de M. Descartes ou le Traité de la Lumière}, Chapter 1). Tickles and pains, as conceived by Descartes, are not incorporations of the extra-somatic so much as conscious modifications of the perceiving subject that do not resemble their external causes. What in the feather resembles the tickle that it prompts? Indeed, it is the conception of sense experience as a conscious modification of the perceiving subject that generates the possibility that the external cause of sense experience may fail to resemble it. However if haptic experience is a kind of incorporation, in the sense that the formal assimilation of haptic experience to its object, relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective, is the result of constitutive shaping, then it is not a conscious modification of the perceiving subject, at least not in Descartes' sense. Vestigial remnants of this conception are the Cartesian core of what Putnam called ``Cartesianism \emph{cum} materialism''. (For a staunch defence of this Cartesian core see \citealt{Farkas:2008aa}.) If haptic perception must be understood in some other way, and is an exemplar of perception more generally, then this aspect of the early modern paradigm must also be rejected.
If the formal assimilation involved in haptic perception is the result of constitutive shaping, then the resulting anti-modern conception of experience does not allow for the possibility of a demon eliminating the object of the perceiver's experience while leaving that experience just as it is. Nevertheless, the anti-modern conception of experience is not, by itself, sufficient to refute skepticism. For skeptical worries may be posed in terms of non-perceptual experiences that appear from within just like the corresponding perceptual experience, consistent with perceptual experiences being constitutively shaped by their objects (Chapter~\ref{sec:perceptual_objectivity}).
% Section shaping (end)
\section{Active Wax} % (fold)
\label{sec:active_wax}
I have claimed that the assimilation at work in grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, is the manifestation, if not the source, of the objectivity of haptic perception. I have also claimed this is part of what makes grasping an apt metaphor for sensory presentation more generally. We are now in a position to elaborate further. Not only does the grasping hand assimilate to the contours of the object, but the perceiver's haptic experience---there where they are handling the object---assimilates to the overall shape and volume of the object as well, at least relative to their haptic perspective on it, the specific manner in which they are handling the object. But one can only assimilate to what is there to be assimilated. The objectivity of haptic perception is thereby manifested. And if this formal assimilation, understood on the model of constitutive shaping, generalizes to other modes of perception, then part of what makes grasping an apt metaphor for perception generally is our consequent understanding of perceptual objectivity. The formal assimilation of haptic experience to its object relative to the perceiver's handling of it, the constitutive shaping of the phenomenological character of that experience by the presentation of its object to the perceiver's haptic perspective, is the manifestation of the objectivity of that haptic perception. But what is its source? What explains haptic experience assimilating to its object? If we bear in mind that haptic experience is where the perceiver is handling the object, then a plausible thought is that it is the force of the hand's activity, the effort exerted in more precisely molding the hand to the contours of the object, that is the source of the hand, and consequently our haptic experience, assimilating to its object. Objective haptic perception is an experience sustained by the hand's activity.
While the assimilation of haptic experience to its object, relative to the perceiver's haptic perspective, is the manifestation of the objectivity of haptic perception, it is the force of the hand's activity that is its source. It is because the hand tightens its grip that it's flexible interior surface may more precisely mold to the object's contours. Molding more precisely to the object's contours ensures that those contours explain the hand's configuration and force. And in molding more precisely to the object's contours, the haptic experience this activity gives rise to formally assimilates to its constituent object.
Robert Kilwardby provides a vitalist twist on the Peripatetic analogy that potentially sheds light on the epistemic significance of the force of the hand's activity in grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception. (On Kilwardby on perception see \citealt{Silva:2008yg,Silva:2010zh,Silva:2012tg}.) Kilwardby composed \emph{De spiritu fantastico sive de recptione specierum} most likely while in Blackfriars in Oxford in the 1250s prior to being elevated to the Archbishop of Canterbury. In a remarkable passage, Kilwardby writes:
\begin{quote}
if you place a seal before wax so that it touches it, and you assume that the wax has a life by which it turns itself towards the seal and by striking against it comes to be like it, by turning its eye upon itself it sees in itself an image of the seal. (Kilwardby, \emph{De spiritu fantastico} 103, \citealt[94]{Broadie:1993dz})
\end{quote}
Kilwardby transform's the Peripatetic analogy by imagining life to inhere in the wax so that it is actively pressing against the seal and so taking its sensible form upon itself. (Kilwardby's image of active wax will be echoed by Peter John Olivi, perhaps independently of Kilwardby, in \emph{Quaestiones in secondum librum Sententiarum} q. 58 415--16, 506--7; q. 72 35--6.)
% The vitalist twist on the wax analogy accomplishes two things. First, in the active wax taking upon itself the sensible form of the seal, the analogy makes intelligible how perception may be a non-material mode of assimilation, an internalization or mode of taking in. But importantly, what sense it provides to this non-material mode of assimilation is consistent with what is assimilated in this way existing and having its character independently of that perception. Indeed, it is the resistance to the wax's activity that discloses the sensible form of the object had prior to perception.
Kilwardby's account is motivated, in no small part, by his conviction, grounded in his reading of Augustine, that the soul cannot be acted upon by the body (\emph{De spiritu fantastico} 47--54, on Augustine's philosophy of mind see \citealt{ODaly:1987fq}, on Augustine's influence on Kilwardby see \citealt{Silva:2010zh}). It is a consequence of the soul's ontological superiority over the corporeal that the latter may never act upon the former. Kilwardby tentatively accepts a Peripatetic model where, in vision, say, the perceived object acts upon the transparent medium such that its image (its likeness, in Scholastic terminology, its species) exists, in some sense, in it, and that the medium, in turn, affects the sense organ such that the image comes to, in some sense, exist in it as well (\emph{De spiritu fantastico} 69, 97). But how does the sensory soul receive the image that informs the sense organ, if the sense organ is precluded, by its corporeal nature, from acting upon the soul?
The vitalist twist on the Peripatetic analogy is meant to address this problem. The sensory soul pervades the sense organ, and animates it, and in so doing makes itself like the external body. So it is the sensory soul that is the efficient cause of the likeness of the body occurring in it. The sensory soul makes itself like the external body by pressing against the sense organ that it animates itself impressed with the image of the object. In actively pressing against the impressed sense organ, the soul makes within itself the image of the external body: ``For in this way the sensory soul, by turning itself more attentively to its sense organ which has been informed by a sensible species, makes itself like the species, and by turning its own eye upon itself it sees that it is like the species'' (\emph{De spiritu fantastico} 103, \citealt[94]{Broadie:1993dz}).
What does the metaphor of the sensory soul pressing against the impressed sense organ mean? Sense can be made of it in terms of Kilwardby's doctrine that the soul's use of a body is limited by the passivities of matter (\emph{De spiritu fantastico} 99--100). So a feather striking a tapir's skull will not break it, but a femur will, even if it is the same hominid striking the skull with equivalent musculature exertion in each instance. The difference is due to the way in which the activity of the agent is limited by the passivities of matter inhering in the body that is being used. A species inhering in a sense organ is among the passivities of matter exhibited by that corporeal body. And Kilwardby explains the soul's assimilation of the sensible form of the perceived object in terms of how the species inhering in the sense organ limits the sensory soul's use of it (Kilwardby \emph{De spiritu fantastico} 103).
% \begin{quote}
% Therefore while the soul attends to the body which is acted upon so that it moves the body according to the requirement of its passivity, <the soul> assimilates itself to what is acted upon according as it is acted upon. But such assimilation is just the formation of the image of a sensible thing by which <formation> the sense organ finds in itself what has been affected, since the affecting of the organ by the sensible object is the being-acted-upon of which we speak. (Kilwardby \emph{De spiritu fantastico} 103, \citealt[94]{Broadie:1993dz})
% \end{quote}
It is not clear whether the subsequent account constitutes a genuine reconciliation of Augustinian and Peripatetic metaphysics (for discussion of Kilwardby on perception see \citealt{Silva:2008yg,Silva:2010zh}; \citealt[Chapter 4]{Silva:2012tg}; selections from \emph{De spiritu fantastico} are also translated in \citealt{Knuuttila:2014rc}). Regardless of Kilwardby's intent, however, and dropping his Augustinian dualism, the hand, the mobile and elastic instrument of haptic exploration, is the active wax in grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception. It is the hand that is actively molding itself to the object in grasping or enclosure. And it is the hand that is thereby taking upon itself a configuration and enclosing a certain volume determined by the overall shape and volume of the object grasped. And it is these activities of the hand that gives rise to the perceiver's haptic experience. In making an effort to mold more precisely to the contours of the rigid, solid body, not only does the hand assimilate to the contours of the object grasped, but the perceiver's haptic experience---there where the perceiver is handling the object---assimilates to the overall shape and volume of the object presented in it.
Further, I take it that it is at least part of Kilwardby's suggestion that it is the activity of the wax and the resistance it encounters in pressing against the seal---the passivities of matter that limits its activity---that discloses the shape of the seal had prior to perception. So if the hand is the active wax in grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, then it is the force of the hand's activity and the resistance it encounters in maintaining simultaneous contact with a non-insignificant portion of the object's overall surface that discloses the tangible qualities of the object had prior to that haptic encounter. Kilwardby's suggestion, then,---if released from the confines of Augustinian metaphysics, if, in turn, narrowly confined to haptic presentation---is that the presentation of tangible qualities of objects external to the perceiver's body is due, at least in part, to the activity of the hand in grasping and the felt resistance it encounters. The hand, and haptic experience in turn, only assimilate to the tangible aspects of the rigid, solid body thanks to the force of the hand's activity in conflict with the self-maintaining forces that constitute the categorical bases of that body's solidity and rigidity. At least with grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, perceptual realism is sustained by the force of the hand’s activity in conflict with the self-maintaining forces of the object grasped. It is only in this way is it ensured that the tangible qualities determined by the self-maintaining forces of the object grasped explains the configuration and force of the grasping hand.
% Section active_wax (end)
\section{A Puzzle} % (fold)
\label{sec:a_puzzle}
% To fully appreciate the epistemic significance of the force of the hand's activity in more precisely molding to the contours of the object grasped, we need an account of how it is that assimilating to an external body discloses the tangible qualities that inhere in that body prior to haptic perception. The question here is a ``how possible'' question \citep{Cassam:2007lq}. How is objective haptic perception so much as possible?
In discussing the objectivity of grasping, understood as a mode of haptic perception, we supposed that it is our hand's configuration in grasping and the force that needs to be exerted in maintaining that configuration that discloses the overall shape and volume of the object grasped. The hand is, in this way, the active wax in haptic perception. I believe this supposition to be both plausible and true, but once it is clearly stated, a puzzle immediately arises.
Embodiment is a fundamental feature of animal existence and so a fundamental feature of the existence of primates like ourselves. So much so, that many philosophers take animality to be the key to our very identity (for a recent statement see \citealt{Snowdon:2014ta}). An animal's awareness of its body is a mode of self-presentation. There may be more to an animal than is revealed in bodily awareness, but bodily awareness nevertheless presents corporeal aspects of the animal whose awareness it is. Bodily awareness remains a mode of self-presentation even if its disclosure of the animal whose awareness it is is partial in this way. Let bodily awareness be understood broadly enough to comprise both proprioception and kinesthesis and potentially more besides. So bodily awareness affords the perceiver with, among other things, awareness of the configuration of their limbs as well as awareness of their motion. So understood, awareness of the hand's configuration in grasping and awareness of the force that needs to be exerted in maintaining that grasp are both modes of bodily awareness. And since bodily awareness is a kind of self-presentation, so are awareness of the hand's configuration and awareness of the force exerted in maintaining it.
Our puzzle now is this. How can a mode of self-presentation disclose the presence of some other thing? After all, perceivers, in being aware of their body, in presenting only themselves, present no other thing. So how can bodily awareness be leveraged into disclosing the presence of something external to the perceiver's body? What alchemy transmutes bodily sensation into tactile perception?
Our puzzle concerns whether grasping so much as could be a mode of haptic perception. Though our interest is presently restricted to grasping as a mode of haptic perception, we can, however, get a better sense of that puzzle by considering an analogous case. So consider felt temperature. Contrast two cases. In both cases you feel warm, and you feel warm to the same degree. But in the first case, you feel warm because of a fever, and in the second case, you feel warm because because of the ambient heat. In both cases, your body is warmed. They differ only in the source of the warmth, with whether the warmth of your body is internally or externally generated. And in both cases, you feel equally warm. Nevertheless, a phenomenological difference remains. In the second case, not only do you feel warm, but you feel, as well, the warmth in the ambient air. Indeed, the warmth you feel is in conformity with the warmth felt in the ambient air. What explains this phenomenological difference? How are tangible qualities felt in something external to the perceiver's body such that perceiver feels in conformity with such qualities?
The puzzle is not meant to underwrite skepticism about haptic perception or tactile perception more generally. We are taking it for granted that in grasping a stone, say, our hominid ancestor feels the overall shape and volume of that stone. We are taking it for granted that grasping is a mode of haptic perception that affords the perceiver awareness of tangible qualities that inhere in the object grasped. Our puzzle is not meant to underwrite skepticism about whether grasping is a genuine mode of haptic perception so much as to underwrite a ``how-possible'' question \citep{Cassam:2007lq}. How is it that the configuration of the hand and the force exerted in maintaining that configuration disclose the overall shape and volume of the object grasped? How is objective haptic perception so much as possible? The puzzle, then, is at best proof of an explanatory lacuna rather than proof of the impossibility of objective haptic perception.
There is an aspect of grasping or enclosure that has so far remained implicit in our discussion of it but is crucial for refining our how-possible question in such a way as to point toward an adequate solution. The perceiver, in exerting effort in more precisely molding their hand to the contours of the object grasped, encounters felt resistance to their efforts. It is because the self-maintaining forces of the body resist the hand's encroachment that the hand can assimilate to the body's contours. The forces that constitute the body's solidity ensure that the force of the grasping hand does not penetrate it. And the forces that constitute the body's rigidity ensure that it maintains its overall shape and volume despite the force of the hand's grasp. Maybe it is the hand's encounter with felt resistance---the activity of the wax limited by the passivities of matter---that discloses the tangible qualities of an external body. The suggestion, here, is not merely that the puzzle overlooked the contribution of cutaneous activation to tactile awareness, but rather with how cutaneous activation interacts with kinesthesis and bodily awareness more generally in giving rise to the experience of an external limit to the body's activity. If among the objects of bodily awareness are limits to the body's activity, a question arises whether bodily awareness is exhaustively understood as a mode of self-presentation. In presenting a limit, does not one, implicitly at least, present, as well, what lies beyond that limit? Thus, in presenting a limit to the body's activity, bodily awareness is more than a mere mode of self-presentation. (We shall return to this issue in Chapter~\ref{sec:sensing_limits}.) While the initial formulation of the how-possible question relied on the assumption that bodily self-awareness is a mere mode of self-presentation, the refined how-possible question that will guide us from hereon out dispenses with that assumption.
Smith has appropriated Fichte's term, \emph{Anstoss}, for the way in which the experienced limitation of the body's activity can disclose sensible aspects of an external body:
\begin{quote}
Although neither touch sensations nor the active / passive distinction suffices for perceptual consciousness, when the two are taken together we \emph{do} find something that suffices \ldots\ Although no mere impact on a sensitive surface as such will give rise to perceptual consciousness, \emph{we} certainly feel objects impacting on us from without. This fact needs to be recognized in any adequate perceptual theory. I shall name the phenomenon that is central here by the term that is at the heart of Fichte's treatment of the ``external world,'' or the ``not-self'': the \emph{Anstoss}. This phenomenon is that of a \emph{check} or \emph{impediment} to our active movement; an experienced obstacle to our animal striving, as when we push or pull against things. \citep[153]{Smith:2002sa}
\end{quote}
Part of what we shall learn from the refined how-possible question is that \emph{Anstoss}, at least as Smith conceives of it, is itself subject to further explanation (elaborating that explanation is the task of the next Chapter).
Influenced by Fichte, Maine de Biran applies this conception to grasping or enclosure, understood as a mode of haptic perception, thus:
\begin{quote}
If---the object still remaining on my hand---I wish to close the hand, and if, while my fingers are folding back upon themselves, their movement is suddenly stopped by an obstacle on which they press and thwarts them, a new judgment is necessary: \emph{this is not I}. There is a very distinct impression of solidity, of resistance, which is composed of thwarted movement, of an \emph{effort} that I make, in which I am \emph{active} \ldots\ (Maine de Biran, \emph{Influence de l'habitude sur la facult\'{e} de penser}, 1803; \citealt[57]{Boehm:1929aa})
\end{quote}
It is the experienced limit to the hand's activity, a felt resistance to touch, that discloses the presence of a material object external to the perceiver's body.
There is a long history connecting objectivity to felt resistance to touch. In the \emph{Sophist}, Plato recasts the Gigantomachy, the struggle for political supremacy over the cosmos between the Olympian Gods and the Giants, as a metaphysical dispute. The Gods, or Friends of the Forms, insist that only imperceptible forms are most real. Against them, the Giants, the offspring of Gaia, insist that only bodies than can be handled and offer resistance to touch are real:
\begin{quote}
One party is trying to drag everything down to earth out of heaven and the unseen, literally grasping rocks and trees in their hands, for they lay hold upon every stock and stone and strenuously affirm that real existence belongs only to that which can be handled and offers resistance to the touch. (Plato, \emph{Sophist} 246a; Cornford in \citealt[990]{Hamilton:1989fk})
\end{quote}
For the Giants, felt resistance to touch has become a touchstone for reality. Only that which can be handled and offers resistance to touch is real. Even if one rejects the corporealist metaphysics of the Giants, one can accept that the experience that grounds their corporealist conviction is phenomenologically compelling. It would have to be to elicit such cosmic conviction. Grasping something which offers resistance to touch is a phenomenologically vivid and primitively compelling experience of what is external to us.
The phenomenologically vivid and primitively compelling experience of felt resistance to touch will underwrite the dramatic episode involving Dr Johnson outside of a church in Harwich:
\begin{quote}
After we came out of the church, we stood talking for some time together of Bishop Berkeley’s ingenious sophistry to prove the non-existence of matter, and that every thing in the universe is merely ideal. I observed, that though we are satisfied his doctrine is not true, it is impossible to refute it. I never shall forget the alacrity with which Johnson answered, striking his foot with mighty force against a large stone, ’till he rebounded from it, ``I refute it thus.'' This was a stout exemplification of the first truths of Pere Buffier, or the original principles of Reid and Beattie; without admitting which, we can no more argue in metaphysicks, than we can argue in mathematicks without axioms. To me it is inconceivable how Berkeley can be answered by pure reasoning \ldots\ \citep[\textsc{i} 471]{Boswell:1935fk}
\end{quote}
The reality of external matter was demonstrated in the resistance it offered to Dr Johnson’s foot, which rebounded despite its mighty force. It was a demonstration not in the sense of proof, since it is inconceivable how Berkeley can be answered in pure reasoning. Moreover, what was stoutly exemplified was metaphysically axiomatic, a first truth, but proof proceeds from axioms, it does not establish them. Rather Dr Johnson’s performance was a demonstration of first truths by showing or exhibiting them. (On the character of Johnson’s refutation of Berkeley see \citealt{Patey:1986uq}). Dr Johnson's demonstration, like the Giants' before him, draws its dramatic power from the phenomenologically vivid and primitively compelling experience of felt resistance to touch. And this remains true even if the dramatic power of that gesture is all but exhausted in the twentieth century clich\'{e} of the exasperated, table-pounding realist.
Campbell, in his contribution to \citet[71]{Campbell:2014aa}, argues, instead, that Dr Johnson's demonstration was essentially multimodal, depending not only upon the kicking of the stone but upon seeing it as well:
\begin{quote}
It is important that Johnson's kicking the rock is a multimodal affair. It would not have had the same visceral impact if Johnson had rebounded off the thing while kicking it in the pitch dark. That would merely have established the presence of some force or another. (Campbell in \citealt[71]{Campbell:2014aa})
\end{quote}
To be sure, Dr Johnson's performance would have no impact on his audience (Bos\-well, and by extension, us, as recipients of his eye-witness account) if no one saw his demonstration of a first truth or original principle. Recall, his performance is a demonstration in the sense that it showed or exhibited first truths or original principles. So the demonstration, involving Dr Johnson's activity addressed to an audience, was essentially multimodal. But it does not follow that haptic component of that demonstration merely presented some force or another.
% (Perhaps fortuitously, ``demonstration'' derives from the Latin \emph{monstrare} meaning to show, to exhibit, to point out.)
There is more to the experience of kicking a stone in the dark than Campbell allows. For example, despite the darkness, Dr Johnson, perhaps through the reverberation of his foot, which rebounded despite its mighty force, might discern that it was stone and not a log that he was kicking. The characteristic density of stone as opposed to wood might be felt in this manner. And if it is sufficiently cold, he might feel the coldness of the stone through the leather of his boot. So it is not true that all that kicking the stone in the dark presents is some force or another. It can present as well material and thermal qualities of the object kicked.
Campbell underestimates the experience of kicking a stone in the dark in a further and more fundamental way. Not only would that experience establish the presence of some force or another, it would disclose the self-maintaining forces that constitute a rigid, solid object external to Dr Johnson's body. If Dr Johnson's exasperation merely grew with the rebounding of his foot, he might kick it again. But as exasperated as he was in the dark, Dr Johnson's haptic experience presents him with the same stone kicked twice. Each kicking of the stone constitutes distinct haptic perspectives on that object, and Dr Johnson has the capacity to haptically reidentify the stone presented to distinct haptic perspectives, distinct kickings in the dark. Notice that this would not be possible if kicking the stone in the dark merely presented some force or another. Earlier in \citet[26]{Campbell:2014aa}, however, and more plausibly to my mind, Campbell claimed that it was ``the obstinance of the rock, its resistance to the will'' that manifest its mind independence. But surely the obstinance of the rock, its resistance to the will, the effect of the rock's self-maintaining forces which reveal it to be mind-independent matter, was manifest in Dr Johnson's haptic encounter with it independently of being seen. Moreover, it would have to be, if Dr Jonson's performance is to constitute a genuine demonstration wherein a first truth or original principle is shown or exhibited to an audience. Dr Johnson's demonstration, an activity directed to an audience, may be multimodal, but the visceral impact upon the audience depends upon their sympathetically responding to what is present in Dr Johnson's haptic experience.
Campbell may be wrong about what the experience of kicking a stone in the dark may disclose, but a mystery remains as to how Dr Johnson may feel the characteristic density of a stone and its coldness in an external body, or how he may have the experience of kicking the same stone twice. That is to say, it remains a mystery how haptic perception is so much as possible. How does felt resistance to touch disclose tangible qualities inhering in external bodies prior to perception? After all, not all limitations to the body's activity are due to its interaction with external bodies. Not all passivities of matter that limit the hand's activity are external to the perceiver's body. There are internal limitations to the body's activity as well. We encounter an internal limitation to the body's activity due to fatigue or in an inability to touch one's toes. And \citet[154]{Smith:2002sa} gives the nice example of separating your index and middle fingers until you can no more. So not every experience of a limitation to the body's activity is due to the tangible qualities inhering in an external body prior to perception. The problem, then, is a failure of sufficiency. So how is it that in grasping, or enclosure, the experienced limitation to the hand's activity in molding more precisely to the contours of the object grasped discloses that object's overall shape and volume? How does the experienced limitation to the hand's activity become, in haptic perception, an experience of the tangible qualities of an external body? How is it that by means of an experienced limitation to the hand's activity tangible qualities are felt in something external to the perceiver's body and felt in conformity with those qualities?
% In exerting effort to mold more precisely the hand to the contours of the object grasped, in assimilating to the object, the perceiver experiences felt resistance to touch, they experience a limit to the hand's activity. How, in grasping a rigid, solid body, does the limit to the hand's activity---the passivities of matter constraining the active wax in haptic perception---disclose its overall shape and volume?
This, then, is the refined version of our how-possible question: How is it possible for felt resistance to the hand's activity in grasping or enclosure to disclose a rigid body's overall shape and volume? How does the experience limitation to the hand's activity allow the perceiver to feel something in an external body and in conformity with it? Earlier I claimed that the refinement of our question could point toward an adequate solution. Indeed, we have all but stated it. Though perhaps that can only be appreciated once the solution is clearly in view.
% Section a_puzzle (end)
% Chapter grasping (end)